THE LIBRARY The Ontario Institute for Studies in Education X Toronto, Canada LOTZE'S OUTLINES OF PHILOSOPHY ii PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION OUTLINES PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION DICTATED PORTIONS LECTURES OF HERMANN LOTZE TRANSLATION EDITED BY GEORGE T. LADD PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN YALE COLLEGE BOSTON: PUBLISHED BYJ5INN & COMPANY. 1886. Entered, according to Act of Congress, in the year 1885, by GEORGE T. LADD, in the office of the Librarian of Congress, at Washington. J. S. GUSHING & Co., PRINTERS, 115 HIGH STREET, BOSTON. EDITOR'S PREFACE. THIS translation of Lotze's 'Outlines of the Philosophy of Religion ' is made from the German of the second edition, for the revision of which, as well as for that of the first German edition, Professor Rehnisch of Gottingen is responsible. In preference to the first edition, the second was selected, because it seems to be at once more compact (if that were possible) and more compre hensive. It is composed of the dictated portions of the Lectures given in the Summer-Semester of 1875 and the Winter-Semester of 1878-79. The first eight chapters belong to the earlier date ; and, in fact, the course of 1875 closed with them. It was not until the year 1878 that Lotze added to this course the instruction on Religion and Mo rality (Chapter IX.) and on Dogmas and Confessions (Chapter X.). In choosing this volume for the second place in the series of translations of these Outlines, I have been guided to a considerable extent by my own convenience as a teacher. It will be found to be very closely connected with, and indeed founded upon, the conclusions already made accessible in VI EDITOR S PREFACE. the translation of the ' Outlines of Metaphysic.' The Philosophy of Religion is, of course, primarily a speculative or theoretical treatment of the proofs for the Being of God, of his Attributes, and of his Relations to the World of matter and of finite spirits. But Lotze's metaphysical thinking leads him to the conclusion that the source and centre and sum of all that Reality with which it is the business of Metaphysic to deal, is the Personal Absolute whom — to use the language of Tren- delenburg — "faith calls God." The Philosophy of Religion must therefore first derive from Meta physic the results of a critical treatment of those assumptions concerning all that is Real, which enter into all experience ; it must afterwards dis cuss these same assumptions in that expanded form which is the result of taking into the ac count the content of a further special experience of an aesthetic, ethical, and definitively religious kind. Readers who have not already made them selves somewhat familiar with the author's views on metaphysical questions, should, in studying this volume, recur constantly to the ' Outlines of Meta physic,' or to the larger volume on Metaphysic in his ' System of Philosophy.' It is my earnest hope that a large number" of those whose work it is to teach religion will make EDITOR S PREFACE. vii a somewhat careful study of this brief philosophi cal treatise. It seems to me admirably adapted for an exercise in that fundamental thinking on the most important of subjects presented to the human reason, which no one can safely despise, and which few are in a position wisely to neglect. It is surely when applied to such subjects, if at all, that Philosophy may make good her claim to the ancient title which ascribed to her something of the ' divine.' It is scarcely necessary for me to repeat what was said in the Preface to the ' Outlines of Meta- physic ' ; namely, that my office is solely that of an interpreter, and not at all that of a critic or judge, — favorable or unfavorable to any views of the author. One remark, however, may properly be added, simply with a view to guard those readers who are not familiar with the writings of Lotze, against impressions that might lead to mis understanding him. This entire treatise is avow edly designed to inquire "how much of the con tent of religion may be discovered, proved, or at least confirmed, agreeably to reason " (see p. 2). It is an effort to treat of " Religion within the limits of mere reason." But it is also avowedly very far from that " barren rationalism " which overlooks the 'aesthetic' (in the widest sense) VJ11 EDITOR S PREFACE. elements of human nature (p. 6 f.) ; it makes con stant reference to, and attempts to afford satis faction for, our indestructible religious needs. Par ticularly in the last two chapters, therefore, it should be remembered, that what may be said to be, ' speculatively ' considered, either determinable or unknowable, is by no means necessarily the same when considered from the point of view occupied by the investigator of the specific truths of Biblical revelation. In other words, a large amount of speculative agnosticism is not incom patible with a firm conviction as to the truthful ness of the system of doctrines called Scriptural, and scientifically formulated by dogmatics. The first translation of this volume, with the exception of Chapters II. to IV., was made by L. O. Brastow, D.D. : the editor is responsible for the translation of those three chapters and for the revision of the whole. The nature of both the subject and its treatment has made it pos sible to present this one of the series, with the exception of certain distinctively metaphysical por tions, in a form more easily intelligible to most readers than was possible in the case of the 'Outlines of Metaphysic.' GEORGE T. LADD. NEW HAVEN, January, 1885. TABLE OF CONTENTS. PAGE INTRODUCTION i CHAPTER I. — The Proofs for the Existence of God j^/' 8 II. — More precise Determinations of the Abso lute ....... 35 III. — The Metaphysical Attributes of God . 45 IV. — Of the Personality of the Absolute . 55 V. — Of the Conception of Creation ... 70 VI. — Of Preservation 81 VII. — Of Government . ..... 95 VIII. — Of the Conception of the World-Aim . 114 IX. — Religion and Morality .... 129 X. — Dogmas and Confessions . . . 143 INTRODUCTION. § 1. If religion were a normal product of the human reason alone, then philosophy would be the sole legitimate organ for determining and interpreting its content. If, on the contrary, it sprung from revelation, then reason alone would not be able, it is true, to have discovered it ; but after it were in exist ence, it would still be necessary to show that its content is the adequate fulfilment for those re ligious needs which our reason is compelled to cher ish, but would not be able of itself to satisfy. Even in this case, therefore, philosophy would have a work to accomplish by way of such authenticating. The assertion that the content of religion is a 'mystery' is not convincing. There can be many facts of religion of such sort that the possibility of their coming to pass may not admit of rational apprehension ; and yet we should not without ex: ception take offence at this. But a ' mystery,' the significance of which were not at least sus ceptible of definition, would be a mere curiosity devoid of all connection with our religious needs, PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. and, on this account, an unworthy object of reve lation. Finally, if religion were a morbid product of the human spirit, philosophy, even in that case, would find occupation. It would have to investigate psy chologically and historically the conditions of the origin of this delusion, as well as the conditions of avoiding it in the future. The principal object of the following reflections is connected with the first point of view above suggested : that is, we seek to ascertain how much of the content of religion may be discovered, proved, or at least confirmed, agreeably to reason. The two other points of view we subordinate to this. § 2. It is customary to demand faith in contrast with knowledge as the proper organ for the truths of religion. Such an assertion finds its most exact expression in the intimation that, in fact, even scientific cognition always rests ultimately upon ' faith ' ; that is to say, upon an immediate act of trust in certain absolutely simple and self-evident truths, which are neither in need of any proof, nor capable of it. An important distinction is overlooked in the above-mentioned view. All such ultimate, self- THE PROPOSITIONS OF FAITH. evident propositions, upon which our knowledge is founded, are general judgments, which do not tell us that anything whatever is or takes place, but which only declare what would exist or would have to take place, in case definite conditions occur ; or — more concisely — they all merely express certain general rules, which we are obliged to follow in the combination of the content of our ideas. On the contrary, those propositions upon which the most special interest of religion depends, — for example, that God is, that He has created the world, that the soul survives death, etc., — are all of them declarative judgments, which assert a definite, par ticular fact. With respect to the before-mentioned general propositions, it may be understood that they are capable of being objects of our imme diate insight or evidence ; for they are nothing but expressions of the forms of activity, in which our reason according to its own nature must be exer cised. On the other hand, these declarative propo sitions of faith, which assert a fact with respect to the ordering of the world that is foreign to our own nature, cannot with equal legitimacy be re garded as a natural or innate endowment of our spirit, but are in some sort the results of culture. PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. § 3. It would be better to have undertaken a comparison of religious truth and scientific cog nition different from the foregoing. No cognition consists merely of those general propositions of which we. have made mention ; but every cognition originates by means of the application of these prop ositions to a content which only experience can fur nish ; more concisely, it is an elaboration of given perceptions. Now it might be asserted that it is not the external world exclusively which furnishes these necessary data by influence on our senses. Rather is it quite as admissible to think of a divine or supersensible influence upon our interior being, by means of which ' intuitions ' of another species fall to our lot, such as the senses can never supply, and such as constitute just that religious cognition which obtrudes itself upon us with immediate cer tainty. It is to be said in reply to the foregoing claim that, although the aforesaid divine influences are willingly conceded, still, according to the analogy of the ' sense-impressions ' which are brought into comparison with them, they can consist imme diately in nothing but a certain mode of our affec tion, or of our experience, or of our feeling. Now, just as a sense-impression, — for example, a color or a tone, — is after all no ' cognition ' whatever ; ORIGIN OF RELIGIOUS TRUTH. but such a cognition originates only by comparing one impression with others, and by noticing the relations which occur between them, just so would those supersensible impressions consist immediately in mere feelings, moods, or movements of our own mind; but they would still represent in this form no truth of religion. The rather would such a truth, as admits of being expressed in a definite communicable proposition, originate only through the agency of an elaboration in thought of those 'inner experiences' which go back to the 'grounds' of these states of the mind. § 4. The only remnant of any useful result from this opposition of science to faith is, therefore, the conviction that the whole of our knowledge certainly does not originate from external experience, which is mediated for us by the senses ; but that there are also inner states which are available as data for the acquisition of truth. The finishing of the structure of religion depends, not exclusively but chiefly, upon these latter data ; and of such inner states there may be distinguished three groups : — (i) The personal feelings of fear, of absolute dependence on unknown powers, which belong to the most effective, but also to the most crude of the fundamental impulses that urge the mind to PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. seek consolation in a non-empirical view of the world. (2) Then there are the much nobler and just as truly effective aesthetic feelings that yield them selves admiringly to the beautiful which they dis cover in the world, and by means of it are incited to form a picture of an ideal world. This they do without any egoistic interest in the consolation desired ; but rather with the sure conviction that what is so fair and full of significance cannot be an accidental product of that which is without significance, but must be either the very Princi ple of the world or closely related to its creative principle. (3) Finally, there are the ethical feelings, which, without being deducible from 'mere experience,' necessitate the attempt to conceive of a construc tion of the world in which this fact of the moral obligation of the will to a definite form of action finds an intelligible and rational place. If now we conceive of the truth of religion as developed from all these data by means of our reflection, then we certainly get at what might be designated as "Religion within the limits of mere reason," but still not at that which has been so called. For, in most attempts of this kind, the great and weighty influence of the aforesaid aes- CAUSES OF BARREN RATIONALISM. / thetic elements is especially overlooked, and, there by, a very barren rationalism takes the place of that which the whole reason, acting in all directions, would be able to produce. CHAPTER I. THE PROOFS FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD. § 5. The different attempts of reason to attain to certainty concerning the Supersensible, by starting from all the above-mentioned points of departure, are too manifold for direct statement. As often, however, as science has undertaken to give an account of its profits, it has done this in a doctrine of the " Proofs for the existence of God." Accord ingly we also now present these proofs with the design to show how each one of them adopts its own special method for discovering a portion of the supersensible truth ; and with the brief pre liminary remark that these proofs naturally cannot, properly speaking, demonstrate the existence of God as necessary, — that is, as dependent on something else, — but that they are all able merely to demon strate our assumption of this existence as a logi cally necessary consequence of the given facts of the world. § 6. The ontological argument, as ordinarily ap prehended, maintains that, while the conception of other beings does not include their existence, the THE MOST PERFECT BEING. conception of the most perfect Being of all does include it ; and that this being would in fact con tradict its own conception, if the one perfection — to wit, existence itself — did not belong to it. The logical error of this argument is sufficiently well known. Not merely the conception of the most perfect Being, but indeed that of every living or active being (as, for example, the conception of an animal), includes existence also as necessary to be added in thought for defining it ; and without this all the rest of its predicates (e.g., sensation, motion, propagation, etc.) would be quite unthink able. But with respect to no one of these concep tions, does it follow from the necessity of adding in thought this mark (of existence), that after this the total content of the conception thus fully thought -1 has validity in the nature of reality also, and that it may not be a merely thinkable combi nation of our imagination. But although logically this attempt at proof is quite invalid, it is nevertheless of interest in other respects. For that which induces it to regard existence as a necessary attribute of the total content of the conception of the most perfect Being, is not, as it is in the case of the other conception (that of the animal), the mere circum stance that the rest of the predicates would admit IO PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. of formal attachment to what is existent only, and not to what is non-existent. This is obviously rather a case where an altogether immediate con viction breaks through into consciousness ; to wit, the conviction that the totality of all that has value — all that is perfect, fair, and good — can not possibly be homeless in the world or in the realm of actuality, but has the very best claim to be regarded by us as imperishable reality. This assurance, which properly has no need of proof, has sought to formulate itself, after a scholastic fashion, in the above-mentioned awkward argument. § 7. The cosmological argument begins in an ap prehension of frequent occurrence, yet withal wholly incorrect ; namely, that the existence of each indi vidual Thing and of the world in general is contin gent, and therefore presupposes not a contingent but a necessary Being. At this point, the particular conceptions which are wrongly attached to this thought, must be first subjected to a definition. The ordinary use of language is not at all ac quainted with the philosophic significance of the word 'contingent,' according to which it is applicable to every existing thing whose non-existence in gen eral would be thinkable without contradiction, and whose conception or whose nature accordingly offers IDEA OF THE 'CONTINGENT.' II no resistance to the cessation of its own existence. Rather does the common usage in the first instance merely contrast the ' contingent ' with the designed, and understands by it all those secondary effects which, without being themselves designed, originate from action of ours that is designed. This happens because our actions themselves are for the most part capable of accomplishment only by means of some change in the objects of the external world ; these objects, however, because of those relations inde pendent of ourselves in which they stand to each other, cannot be changed by us without propagating still further in various directions the impressions they have received. We speak, furthermore, of ' contingent ' events, when* we have directed our attention to a general law of nature and when, in its application to a single case, processes occur which do not follow from the law and from the circumstances necessary for its application, but only from the accessory cir cumstances that are foreign to the law. Even such a 'contingent,' as well as the preceding, is, wherever it occurs, necessary and inevitable, and is constantly conditioned by its own adequate reasons ; only these reasons do not reside in the design nor in the law. Finally, we also call such facts 'contingent' as 12 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. are assumed by us not to be predestinated in such a plan of the world's course as we have rightly or wrongly presupposed, but only to originate inci dentally through the mechanism of those efficient agencies which are summoned for the accomplish ment of that plan. And with the one just mentioned is connected the still broader use of the word, according to which it becomes a mere determination of value, and desig nates that whose nature and content seem to de serve existence neither on account of its own value nor by connection with other values ; although it, nevertheless, is in possession of such existence. In this sense, the ' contingent ' is simply the matter of fact, whose being does not permit either of deri vation from an effectuating condition, or of justifi cation by its own value. § 8. The other conception, namely, that of the 'necessary,' is, in the only meaning of it which is quite clear to us, completely identical with that of the 'conditioned.' That only 'is' necessary, the ac tuality of which cannot be conceived of as lacking, whenever a definite presupposed condition actually takes place. But it is very easy to understand whence comes the wish to place in opposition to this "condi- IDEA OF THE 'NECESSARY.' 13 tioned necessary " another of a higher sort. For a given c, which must of course exist in case a deter minate b exists, is 'necessary' only in the sense of its being forced. By means of its own nature merely, and without the aid of b, this c would not exist. The ' necessary ' in that higher sense which is sought, would therefore be such an one as is not dependent on anything else for its existence, and consequently is not conditioned. But it is entirely incorrect to persist in designat ing such an unconditioned as is sought for, by the predicate 'necessary.' It must rather be called the absolute matter of fact, which exists for the reason merely that it does exist ; which does not need jior its existence any extraneous condition ; but which, for precisely this reason, can only be an actual and never a necessary existence. § 9. According to the analysis made above, the thoughts of the cosmological argument do not co here well. From the so-called 'contingent,' — i.e. from that which is conditioned by something else external to it, and in just this respect must be called likewise necessary, — it is certainly possible to ascend to the Unconditioned, whose existence is dependent on nothing else ; but for this very reason such an unconditioned is not 'necessary,' 14 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. but merely matter of fact or actual. The desire to find something, which by means of its own nature, made its own existence necessary, is intrinsically beyond the possibility of realization, — as we saw it to be in the case of the ontological argument ; and to this cause was due also the failure of the thought that the Unconditioned which is sought is to be found in a most perfect Being. To that merely actual (not necessary) unconditioned existence, the smallest, meanest, and most insignificant thing has just as good a claim as the most perfect ; and that precisely for the reason that it is an unconditioned existence, and therefore is dependent on no reasons of any kind. In another direction also the cosmological argu ment goes farther than its premises permit. It was legitimate to seek an Unconditioned for the Condi tioned in the world ; but it is an altogether arbi trary leap to assume that this Unconditioned must be One ; and, furthermore, that it can be conceived of only in the form of a single real Being. It is possible that this assumption may be justified subsequently; but just at this point the other as sumption, to which the natural sciences have come through their need of interpreting the world, obvi ously lies much nearer at hand. We refer to the assumption of a very great multiplicity of uncon- A SINGLE UNCONDITIONED BEING. ditionally existing elements, which are independent of each other, and are only subject to a general sphere of laws in accordance with which the mani fold phenomena proceed from their changeable posi tions with respect to each other. One more consideration of a logical character must first qualify this view. It is that we get no insight as to how a single unconditioned being, even though it were in existence, would be able to condition anything else, and therefore serve as the desired initial member in the conditioned series of the world's events. A conclusion or a consequence never follows except from the concurrence of two premises, and not from one premise alone. To the one unconditioned Being, therefore, if aught is to result from it, there would always" have to be added again other accessory circumstances, which do not emanate from it, but which are just as much uncon ditioned : the world therefore would not be depend ent upon one, but upon many unconditioned begin nings. § 10. The teleological argument proposes to make that empirical conformity to an end, which appears in the world, the point of departure for an inference with respect to a single designing and creative rea son, as the supreme cause of the world. l6 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. Let us in the first place investigate the con ception of that which is 'conformable to an end,' as such. This conception is entirely free from ambiguity only when we take our start from the conscious purposes of our own will, which are fixed upon a determinate result as their end. In that case, what is ' conformable to an end ' is the selection or combination of means, which, by their legitimate action, bring about the realization of the aforesaid end. To call those means themselves ' conformable to an end ' is, properly speaking, not correct. They are themselves merely serviceable : that is to say, their nature is in itself calculated for no determinate end whatever, such as we might set for ourselves ; but it is merely of such sort that a useful application of it to our ends be comes possible for us. Now that this ' serviceableness ' or ' accidental conformity ' of things in the world to an end, is of very frequent occurrence, proves nothing further. For when once there exist Things with properties of their own and with established methods of ac tion, it is a matter of course that some of our designs (which themselves, in the last analysis, always amount to the same as some alteration in the states of Things) may be accomplished by means of the activity to which other Things lay IMMANENT CONFORMITY TO END. I/ claim. More than this, however, does not in reality take place. The nature of Things is not so emi nently useful, that it would be sufficient for the ac complishment even of all authorized designs ; and it is not so absolutely useful that it might not serve just as well for the frustration of that which is rational, and for the production of that which is unauthorized. § 11. In contrast with the aforesaid utility, an "immanent conformity to an end" is spoken of, which appears primarily in the individual organisms that have no other end beyond their own existence, but in each one of which all parts are recipro- cally^related as end and means. Such conformity to an end is then transferred from these individ ual organisms to the Universe, as to a "great or ganism." Now we are accustomed to assert that these com posite forms cannot possibly be mere products of the blind co-operation of many elements, without the unity of one controlling design. Such a conclusion is decidedly false. Even supposing a conscious de sign to be demonstrably at work, still the realiza tion of its end is always dependent on the fact, that every particle of this end is likewise the inevita ble and undesignedly necessary product of the co- 1 8 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. operation of the means summoned to aid. The end would not be possible at all if it were impossi ble in accordance with the laws of the mechanism which these means follow ; and it would not be actual, if it were not also necessary in accordance with these laws, at the very instant when the afore said means are applied. But still further : It is supposed that at least the bringing together of the means themselves, into those positions in which they are of necessity com pelled to realize the end, is impossible without a controlling design. But again it may be answered : Even where this design actually exists, it is unable to bring the usable means into those useful posi tions by its own mere volition ; on the contrary, it is able to accomplish this only by summoning physical agencies and forces of a sort similar to the means themselves. Therefore the state attained at any given instant, when the end is accomplished, must be regarded as the necessary resultant of the co operation of these forces at the preceding instant ; and instead of ' an intelligence which might ex plain the state of the case belonging to this pre ceding instant, there may always be substituted a combination of other blind elements and forces which were compelled to have precisely the same result. IMMANENT CONFORMITY TO END. To state the same thing briefly : The completely automatic blind origin even of the system most conformable to an end, is never impossible ; it is only improbable. And now the question comes, what is meant by this latter expression ? § 12. If we take for granted, that an indefinite multitude of different elements act upon one an other entirely in accordance with mechanical laws, and that they were aboriginally in reciprocal mo tions which were not regulated by any design, then there might issue from such conditions innumera ble possible consequences. The forms possessed of an immanent conformity to an end would represent only* a very insignificant number among these pos sible consequences ; and therefore they would have very little probability of coming into existence. But to reason back from this to a design proposing an end, would be valid only in case the forms con formable to the end alone appeared in the world ; and in case those other results that are without an end, or in contradiction to an end, were neither present in experience, nor needed to be assumed even as having existed in the past. Neither of the above-mentioned suppositions cor responds with the facts. In our actual observation there occur innumerable cases of disease and of the 2O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. failure of rational life-ends; — to say nothing what ever of the very many facts and occurrences which, so far as our discernment extends, are at least with out an end, even if they disturb no other end. But with reference to the past we are at liberty to as sume, that at first an innumerable multitude of in harmonious forms, intrinsically hostile to any end, actually emerged from the reciprocal impact of blind elements ; that these forms, however, were not able to maintain themselves in the course of nature, as against the constant assaults from without ; that, on the contrary, only those few held out, which had chanced to be the more fortunate ; that then these fortunate ones exerted more and more a determin ing influence upon the rest ; and that thus gradu ally it has come to pass, that nature runs its course, not indeed in complete perfection and conformity to an end, but after all to such an extent that there still remain but few disturbances or interferences by which the development and perpetuation of the structures that are conformable to an end, is en dangered. In this way, therefore, it would not be unthinkable that an original chaos gradually shaped itself into a nature that is arranged in conformity to ends. INTELLIGENT ELEMENTS OF REALITY. 21 § 13. Moreover, it is not necessary to stop with the altogether meagre assumptions which we have made. If it is once held to be conceivable that a single supreme intelligence may exert an influ ence upon the reciprocal relations of the elements of the world, then similar intelligence may also be imagined as immediately active in all these indi vidual elements themselves ; and, instead of con ceiving them as controlled merely by blindly op erative forces, they may be imagined as animated spiritual beings, who strive after certain states and offer resistance to certain other states. In such case there may be imagined the gradual origin of ever more perfect relations, from the reciprocal action of these elements, almost like the reciprocal action ^of a human society ; and that too without necessarily arriving at the assumption, to which we are here inclined, of a single, supreme, intelligent Being. Our reasoning issues rather in a sort of polytheistic or even pantheistic conception, and that too in quite tolerable agreement with experience. § 14. Against what was said above it may still be objected, that the persistence, the power of self- maintenance, and the equipoise of the more for tunate forms, which we previously admitted to have originated in the blind course of nature, are not 22 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. identical with that conformity to an end, the ad miration for which was our point of departure in the teleological argument. The aforesaid mere equi poise, and the permanence that originates from it, might also belong of themselves to altogether pur poseless forms ; that is to say, to forms whose entire existence would have absolutely no immediate value and no rational significance. Both these character istics however we suppose we recognize in those structures conformable to an end, which we are here making our point of departure. There is a remainder of truth in the above-men tioned view ; but the thought does not prove what it was assumed to prove. To wit, so soon as we confine ourselves simply to admiration for an imma nent conformity to an end, we are in fact scarcely ever able to demonstrate conclusively that the total result which is produced by it is actually anything of absolute value ; — a value which would have to be apprehended either as being generically its own end, or as being such an end as to admit of our understanding that it could have been devised only by a designing wisdom, and that it only, rather than one of its opposites, was worthy of this wisdom. We admire, for example, the stability of the plan etary system ; we believe that only a Providence has been able to choose from among the innumer- MEANS AND END IN ORGANISM. 23 able possible arrangements of its masses, precisely that one on which this stability depends. But it may be questioned whether after all this constant repetition of the same occurrences is, as a matter of course, a supreme end ; and whether it may not rather be a tedious arrangement ; so much so that there might conceivably have been innumerable arrangements, that never occur in the actual world, which the one succession of different developments of the heavenly bodies might have established, — something much more manifold, novel, and inter esting. In plants, after they once exist, everything harmonizes as means and end. But what is the value of their entire existence ? Ends external to themselves, which they serve, are accomplished by them ; Jmt they might possibly have been accom plished by a shorter method. Their own growth and bloom is in the estimate of our understanding an entirely purposeless fact, in which nothing fur ther actually appears than that equipoise which the mechanical course of nature is capable of produc ing, and from which the conformity to an end here assumed should be quite essentially distinguished. The above-mentioned consideration may be ex tended to the world of animals and men : so long as" there are still among the latter so many com plaints about unrealizable ideals, the thought that 24 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. much of the beauty we conceive has no existence will continue to nullify the conclusiveness of the teleological argument. § 15. If we summarize our thoughts, there re mains but one point of a positive character, and this is the conviction that there is in the world at all events a great deal of that which is beautiful and great and excellent, — admiration for which was the point of departure for this teleological argu ment ; and that it is by no means possible to get rid of this argument by deducing all its examples from the undesigned reciprocal actions of innumerable elements, working in accordance with law. By such deduction we merely change the location of that which has value. We are necessitated then to as sert of just that aforesaid original nature of the elements, and of their general laws of action, that they themselves from the very first include within themselves the ground capable of developing that which has value. But the course of thought given above has ut terly failed as an argument for the existence of God. That Intelligence, of which we cannot be wholly rid, admits just as well of being apprehended as a property adhering immanently to all Things ; or even, if one is pleased to seek it outside of Things, FATE OF THE TELEOLOGICAL ARGUMENT. 25 as a multiplicity of spiritual beings or demons, who share with each other in the creation and control of the world. And each of these assumptions really harmonizes better with the immediate impression of experience than the hasty assumption of one only supreme wisdom, from which as their source the imperfections of the world, that in fact are manifest to us, are .much more difficult to compre hend. § 16. The teleological argument was wrecked by the fact that it was unable, with sufficient certainty arid to a sufficient extent, to prove empirically the empirical datum, which it assumed to make its point of departure, — namely, the world's conformity to an end. We attempt therefore to find our point of depart ure in a simpler datum, which is not so doubtful, and which is quite as generally acknowledged. And we attempt to deduce from it, not exactly the existence of God, but a more modest conclusion, which shall serve us as a preliminary condition for that other conclusion. This datum is in substance the assumption that all the elements of the world, without exception, act upon each other, no matter whether adapted to an end or the reverse ; and therefore that each 26 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. exerts influences upon the rest, or, in turn, receives influences from them. So far as our experience extends, it confirms this assumption. The objec tion against it, that we know little of the past, and absolutely nothing of the future, and that even in the present perhaps individual elements do not stand in any relation of reciprocal action with each other, cannot refute the assumption. For this in difference just mentioned between two elements — a and 1> — at the same time that each individual element stands in a relation of reciprocal action with many others, we should after all never be com pelled to regard as a fact devoid of all principle, but as the necessary consequence of the same 'law,' in accordance with which a and 1> exercise the afore said other reciprocal actions. And just so, if in the past or future these actions of the elements with respect to each other, were different from what they are . now ; yet we should not regard even this as a fact independent of conditions, but as conditioned by some fixed law, which sooner or later would demand other actions with the same consistency with which it now demands the ones in question. If what was said above be not acknowledged, but if it were maintained rather that the elements of the world, without any cause, have sometimes acted upon THE ORIGINAL ELEMENTS RELATED. 2/ each other, in general, and at other times not at all, at one time thus and at another time otherwise ; then the very basis for every investigation would be abolished. Such a world would furnish no data whatever for any conclusion, even with respect to an event that is to be anticipated within its own limits merely, still less for any conclusion with re spect to anything external to itself, which might be regarded, as in any sense, its ground, its cause, its end, or its principle. § 17. From the foregoing it follows now that the individual elements, of which the world is com posed, are by no means able to exist as they will ; and that therefore a course of the world cannot be deduced from real beings, which are from the beginning wholly without relation to each other. If, for example, all things were as incomparable with each other or as disparate as perhaps 'red' or ' sweet ' (and nothing would prevent the making of such an assumption, in case each real being is completely independent, and has to pay no regard whatever to all the others), it is evident that no definite result could possibly spring from any rela tion between two such beings (supposing one to be at all able to conceive of such a 'relation') with any more right than any other could claim. For, 28 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. in order that the result in must originate from a and b, while the same result in could- not originate from a and c, it is necessary that there first exist between b and c, not a complete incomparability, but a definite contrariety, or a difference of definite magnitude, — a thing which is not thinkable, unless b and c are comparable. The further development of these considerations would show then, that this comparability must ob tain, not merely between b and c, but between all the real elements of the world ; and this in such manner, that these elements constitute collectively, not members of a single series, indeed, but rather members of a system of series intersecting each other; and also in such manner that it should be possible for one to proceed from the nature of each individual element to the nature of every other, by a definite number of steps, taken within this net work of system. Such a state of the case lies, as a silent assumption, just as if it were utterly im possible to be otherwise, at the foundation of our entire view of the world ; and, on this account, the importance of this wonderful circumstance is com monly overlooked. § 18. It would be over-rash to infer from this, without further question, a common origin for all ALL ELEMENTS ARE COMPARABLE. 2Q these elements. For although this comparableness of theirs seems like a single select case from among many in contrast with the empty possibilities which we might be able to imagine (as, for example, that all the elements were as totally different as ' red,' ' sweet,' or ' warm '), nevertheless there is appli cable to the case no calculation of probabilities, in accordance with which it would be impossible to accept the existence of this particular case as a mere matter of fact independently of a common cause for all the elements. On the contrary, a different conclusion is justi fied. It is not enough that the natures of Things are homogeneous, unless the same natures stand in some other connection besides. From such ho mogeneity it would barely follow what result (c) must originate from the meeting of two beings a and b, — taking it for granted that there were in general some reason why something new must originate, and why the mere existence of a and b and their conjunction could not have been enough. Or, as expressed in other words : The most that fol lows from the comparable natures a and b concerns the result which they are necessitated to produce, or the manner in which they are necessitated to act upon one another ; but it does not follow that they must produce anything whatever, or that they must act at all upon each other. 3O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. In case we draw a conclusion c from two premises a and b, the meaning is as follows : In the unity of our thinking ego, the two thoughts a and b can not appear as states of this ego without the thought c being attached to them, — and this just on account of the nature of this one subject. If, on the other hand, the thought a were conceived by one person, and the thought b by another, then the thought c would not originate as a consequence in either one of the two, although c, and c alone, would be the necessary result of a and b provided they came to gether at all. The case is exactly so with Things. From the mere fact that one Thing a exists, and another b exists, c does not by any means follow, of course ; and this, although c would be the only effect which could follow, provided a and b acted upon each other. We must investigate the ques tion what, in such a case, would correspond to that identity of the thinking subject by means of which the thoughts a and b alone are necessitated to produce a result. § 19. We derive from Metaphysic the conviction, that this fact of the reciprocal influence of two Things a and b is impossible, so long as both were conceived of as entirely self-sufficient and in such sort independent of each other, that a might exist THINGS AS MODES OF ONE BEING. 31 and be what it is, even though b had no existence. It remains a completely insolvable contradiction, that a and b accommodate themselves to each other (that b, therefore, enters into a state p, as soon as a enters into the state a), if a and b have no con cern with each other. We derive moreover from Metaphysic the further conviction, that all middle terms, which are inter polated between a and b, such as the ' transition ' of a ' substance,' of an ' influence,' or of a ' force,' are either essentially inconceivable ideas, or at any rate do not at all explain the action, but always leave unanswered the -same question; namely, how x after its transition from a to b can begin the production of a change in b, — that is to say, how x can act upon b, or how in general one Thing can act upon another. Finally, we derive the conviction that the afore said inconceivableness can be removed only by the negation of the independence of individual Things : a and b cannot be absolutely different beings, but only modifications of one and the same Being M, which is in them all, in a, b, c, d, . . ., the truly Existent ; and which has indeed assumed different forms in all these different Things, but still re mains indivisibly one and the same individual M. If, then, in the single Thing a there occurs a S 32 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. change a, this a is eo ipso, is of itself already be sides a change of M, and has no need first to become such a change. If then we conceive the nature of M as always endeavoring to maintain its own identity, M will now produce within itself a second state p, which occurs as a compensation to a, and in connection with it forms again an expres sion of the whole nature of M. It is not necessary, however, that this p should appear in our observation as a change of a, but it may appear as a change of the other individual Thing b. And this would then be the procedure which we conceive as an "action of a upon b." § 20. For the sake of elucidation the following remark must be added : What this one Being, or — according to the common expression — what 'the Absolute' is, remains, at first completely indeter minate. From the fact of the reciprocal action of individual Things, the only conclusion at which we arrived was that of the necessary unity of this Absolute. What it is, is left for further determi nation. Furthermore, 'in designating Things as "modifi cations of the Absolute," it is to be acknowledged that such an expression contains no explanation whatever of the precise sorUof unity which obtains THINGS AS MODES OF ONE BEING. 33 between Things and the Absolute ; or of the sort of dependence in which they stand with reference to that Absolute. The expression has rather the distinct negative meaning which denies the self- dependence of individual Things. With something of like sort we are frequently compelled to be sat isfied. We are very often obliged, for the purpose of removing a contradiction or of explaining an occurrence, to postulate a fact, with respect to which, however, we are never able to say how it were possible for it to exist, or to have been brought to pass ; — and this, even in case it can be yet more accurately denned than the fact that is just now assumed by us. We postpone to a subsequent chapter whatever more there is to be said upon this point. Finally ; even the elasticity, or self-maintenance, that we attribute to the Absolute, is used in a preliminary way merely as a not unimaginable ex pression to which different significations may be given. It is not necessary to conceive of the reac tions of the Absolute against the changes that occur, as directed, in a merely mechanical way, to the preservation of the status quo ; instead of this, we might assume even an impulse of development in progress towards a definite goal ; and that this impulse, likewise, by means of any state a which 34 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. had originated either elsewhere or in the prosecu tion of this purposeful activity, would occasion the production of a further state p, by which such pur poseful activity would be propagated further. Such an assumption, made in a preliminary way, is a mat ter of indifference. It is certain only that if there is to be any reciprocal action whatever of individual Things, there must be in the Absolute some such consistent sensibility as is necessitated to produce by means of a its consequence p, no matter whether it be for self-maintenance or for progress. CHAPTER II. MORE PRECISE DETERMINATIONS OF THE ABSOLUTE. § 21. It is not our present design to dissect logically the conception of an ' Absolute/ and to lay down the conditions under which aught would be held to be the Absolute or acknowledged as such. As far as this is a matter of interest, it is too difficult for the present moment. Just now we are rather making the attempt to specify by name that which is by its own nature adapted to fulfil the conditions above alluded to ; and, of course, fulfil them in such a way that it can be recognized as the absolute Principle of that world which is given in experience as bare matter of fact. Not to stray too far abroad, we confine ourselves to the two contraries between which it has long been custom ary to distribute the consistence of whatever is actual ; namely, Matter and Spirit. § 22. The assumption that the common substance of the world is only matter, and matter as endowed only with those properties which we in physical science attribute to every portion of the same, 36 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. has probably never been made in earnest by any one. Such an assumption would take upon itself the Difficult problem of showing how, from these mere properties of space-filling, inertia, divisibility, and mobility, all the rest of the world, and therefore even its spiritual constituents, could be developed as a matter of course, — that is to say, as the mere consequences of such properties and without admix ture of any other principle whatever. Now Psychology has compelled us to the convic tion that the states of motion — which can only be considered as events that happen to masses of the kind referred to above — are, as a matter of fact, the occasions upon which there arise in tis spiritual processes, such as sensations or feelings. But in what way these occasions bring after them these results so unlike themselves, is not only not a sub ject of empirical knowledge, but it is even possible to see that we can never reach the point where it would be for us a matter of course that a mode of the motion of these masses, however wondrously intricate, would now have to cease to remain such, and would be necessitated to transmute itself into quite a different process, of sensation or of feeling. According to all the axioms of which we avail our selves elsewhere in the mechanical consideration of SPIRITUAL AND PHYSICAL PROCESSES. 37 nature, from motions alone nothing but a transfer ence, new distribution, propagation or arrest, of motions can originate. A spiritual effect can be attached to them only indirectly ; to wit, by means of the action of the aforesaid physical processes on a subject which, in its own nature, possesses that capacity for the production of psychical processes in which the motions themselves are wanting. As here in the small, so also in the totality of the world, a Principle of barely material nature would be in no condition to produce from itself the world of spiritual processes. § 23. Now although, each of these two series of events, the spiritual and the physical processes, re quires its own peculiar ' ground ' in reality, it i? nevertheless not necessary that the 'ground' of the two be divided into two different species o/ reality, in such a manner that there may be mate rial Things devoid of all spiritual susceptibility, and spirits devoid of all physical property and activity. The rather may we first examine the thought that both of these original properties are in fact insep arably united in every existence ; and that, on ac count of one of them, the Existent is able to appear as, and to pass for, matter ; while, on account of the other, contrariwise, it leads an inner life and develops spiritual states within itself. 38 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. For the psychology of the individual being, this assumption, on closer inspection, is shown to be un productive. For the consideration of the world as a whole it, at first, has more to recommend it ; and it forms the text of the spirited descriptions in which Pantheism glorifies the unresting life of the eter nally One Substance, both corporal and spiritual, which in ceaseless vicissitude fashions its individual shapes, and lets them be absorbed again into itself. The more definite formulating of these thoughts, in the case of Spinoza and Schelling, arouses our scruples against them. When the former (Spinoza) ascribes to the Absolute innumerable kinds of doing and acting (' Attributes ') that admit of no compari son with each other, — of which, to be sure, only two, namely Thought and Extension (cogitatio and extensid) are familiar to us men, — such manifold- ness obviates in some degree, at least for the imagination, the difficulty which lies in the sin gular circumstance, that just those two attributes which are not reducible to each other are assumed to form the essence of all the Existent. To find, however, for both of these attributes a still ' higher common root,' from which both issued as mere con sequences, but did not themselves constitute such root (so Schelling,) is a problem that surpasses all human power of comprehension. It is indeed pos- THE ABSOLUTE AS SPIRIT. 39 sible to fashion the name of such a ' First Absolute,' which is neither real nor ideal, and )tet is the ground of both. But it is not possible to discover any thing in the entire world, of which it could be said that it belongs to this thing, by virtue of its own nature, to be esteemed as such a common root. Since, therefore, the goad of this Dualism cannot be got rid of, and a substance that is merely real and acts blindly does not suffice for explaining the world, we find herein one of the motives that lead us to the opposite attempt, — to the pure Spiritual ism which undertakes to comprehend the spirit alone as truly existent, and all else as its product. § 24. The above-mentioned views, on being carried out further, are wont by preference to invalidate yet more the spiritual element of the Absolute. Such views customarily announce this element as a rea son that is 'per se unconscious ' ; that only in indi vidual points of its extreme altitude, in individual spiritual beings, raises itself to consciousness. Such a form of conception as the foregoing ap pears inadmissible. We have no right to strip off from the Reason, which we invariably first learn by experience to know as conscious, this predicate of consciousness, and then persuade ourselves that aught intelligible is left still remaining. Rather is 4O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. it true that only one definite thought admits of being connected with the expression, a reason act ing unconsciously in the world ; to wit, the thought that blind forces act in the world, which are not in any respect reason, but which in fact act so that their results are the same as those which a reason acting in the world would have been compelled to desire. At this point the additional misfortune comes to view, that the aforesaid proposition does not ad mit of being proved with reference to any kind of nature's action. For, in order to do this, it were necessary to show that the results of her action are the fulfilment of those absolute ends which reason would have been, not merely able to propose to itself, but compelled to propose as the ones justified in the highest degree. If, on the contrary, we appraise what is actually achieved in nature at a lower value, and assume that it could have been still better, but is not so, then we should be quite as much justified in speaking of an treason acting blindly in the world. But apart from this, it is clear according to what was said above, that a self-conscious reason could never originate as a final product from such powers ; rather should we have to be satisfied with uncon sciousness throughout the entire world. IMPERSONAL SPIRIT IMPOSSIBLE. 4! It is wrong also to appeal to the analogy of our own spirit, which, without conscious design, in stinctively produces many of its rational works ; such, for example, as those of art. We admit the existence of such activities ; but we know of them in absolutely no other case than that of spirits whose nature it is to be self-conscious : moreover, they appear in this case as actions ac companying or following excitations and states which were originally possible only in conscious ness, but which in time vanish from consciousness by reciprocal inhibition. How, on the other hand, anything similar could take place in a subject, in whose nature no consciousness had ever preceded such activities, is not in the slightest degree com prehensible. § 25. In connection herewith, the same view is fond of speaking of an impersonal Spirit. This, too, is much easier to say than by it men tally to represent anything. It is quite correct that, in our own spiritual life, we experience manifold states in which all attention to our own self, and all positing of that self over opposite to an external world, are completely gone ; and we so lose ourselves in the content of a sensation, an idea, a feeling, or an effort, that we (so to 42 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. speak) are for a time nothing but this, as it were, self-apprehending content, and not a subject which had this content as an object of its consciousness and distinguished it from itself. But it is just as certain that we know such states only as occurrences in an otherwise per sonal spirit. They merely prove that it is not necessary for the personal spirit at every moment to think of itself as different from the content which exactly fills out its consciousness. But they cannot prove that anything similar is possible without the personality, which, in such a case, does not indeed mentally represent itself, but none the less remains in fact the condition of the possibility of such a self-forgetfulness. For all the aforesaid sensations, ideas, or feelings, in which we thus lose ourselves, are after all never thinkable except as states of a definite, self-identical and separate spiritual subject ; and not the least consecutiveness, nor any coherency according to law between these different spiritual states, would be possible, unless the personal unity of the spirit, which is by no means apparent in them, were for all that the real ground which unites them with one another. IMPERSONAL SPIRIT IMPOSSIBLE. 43 § 26. It. is further adduced in support of the above-mentioned view that even the 'personality' with which we have an acquaintance, — to wit, that of the human soul, — first originates in the course of its development. As originally given there exist, it is said, only common spiritual capa cities which, by means of favorable circumstances, are aroused to expression in such manner that, from the combination of these expressions, a reflection directed toward self and a self-con sciousness can also originate. Just so, it is claimed, the Absolute at first is impersonal Spirit. At this point views are di vided : one makes the Absolute, just like the finite spirit, attain to a personality of its own ; the other makes it always remain of itself imper sonal and only assume personal form in individual ones ,of its products, that is in finite spirits. The first view is for the present time a useless curiosity. For us it would hardly be of any value religiously, that the Absolute has attained to personality at the conclusion of its develop ment. On the contrary, an account of the way in which this result is reached is demanded by no religious need, but at the very most only by speculative curiosity. The other view would be compelled to assert 44 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. that the Absolute, of itself unconscious and imper sonal, produces even in its blind development the favoring conditions under which its own products, the finite spirits, developed the personality denied to itself. This is likewise an opinion that answers to no religious need ; and least of all to the neces sity of making intelligible from a single real prin ciple, not merely the external course of the world, but also its moral order, and the fact that it fur nishes us with obligatory ideals of the Good and the Holy. In this way it is made apparent that very pow erful motives impel the religious spirit, at last, straight to the conception of a personal God, and do not permit it to shrink back from the many difficulties that lie in this conception also. CHAPTER III. THE METAPHYSICAL ATTRIBUTES OF GOD. § 27. We abandon the previous train of thought and now consider the conception of God as, on the basis of the incentives depicted in the last chapter, by means of a long spiritual labor of the centuries and essentially harmonious, it lies before us perfected in the monotheistic religions. We consider, first, the formal or metaphysical deter minations. That God is but One, and that polytheism is therefore excluded, we pass with a bare allusion. Many Gods, if each lived independent in his own world, would be a useless and adventurous thought ; but if they met each other with their activity in one and the same -world, then they would necessarily be finite beings, which acted on each other and suffered effects from each other in accordance with certain laws appointed over them. The religious nature does not understand the ' Unity of God ' in the aforesaid numerical mean ing. It does not intend to affirm that God is in fact only one, while by way of imagination 46 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. there might possibly be beside him still others of his own kind. It means rather that God is an only God ; that is to say, there is no superior general concept of a God, of such sort that all the predicates which might belong to the actual God as an example of this concept of species, would ensue from it just as much conditioned and prescribed as in the case of every finite creature, from whose concept of species ensues the limit within which its properties and their reciprocal combination can vary. This absolute independence of the Highest Prin ciple, which does not admit of its being in any way subordinated to one still higher, — as though it were effect or even mere example of the latter, — will appear to us subsequently in the different consequences which are to be drawn from it, as one of the most important of the formal deter minations. § 28. To a second formal predicate, that of Unchangeableness, the religious feeling does not attach the same meaning as seems to accord with this title. Perfectly unchangeable substances would, of course, be philosophically useless assumptions even for the explanation of nature ; but still, if one THE PREDICATE OF OMNIPRESENCE. 47 chooses to avoid certain questions as to first prin ciples, such substances always admit of being em ployed for the intermediate explanation of processes one from the other. A God, on the contrary, who should be without changeable inner states forever perfectly self-identical, would answer to no religious need. We need, in brief, a living God ; and, there fore, by his ' unchangeableness ' nothing further is meant than the consistency with which all these inner states proceed from a nature that remains the same. On this point we are in accord with Metaphysic also, which requires of the nature of all substances — even of such as are finite — only this consistent exclusiveness of the series of forms within which each being among them varies ; it does not, however, require the monotony and rigid ity of a perfect unchanging self-likeness. § 29. A third formal predicate, Omnipresence, seems only at first sight to ascribe to God an at tribute of spatiality such as we otherwise impute merely to matter. The religious meaning of this expression signifies rather the opposite. Concerning finite things we know that if they act upon each other immediately, it is only when in spatial contact, and therefore where they are ; 48 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. on the contrary, if they act at a distance, it is only mediately (by means of the propagation of their first action to elements lying between) : or we know that, if we concede to them an immediate action from afar, this action at least has its maximum when the nearness is greatest, and diminishes as the distance increases. Both limitations are supposed not to be true of God. If he wills to act upon any element of the world, then his activity is supposed not to have to traverse any way, long or short, up to the point where such element exists. Conversely, if an ele ment of the world — for example, a finite spirit with his prayer — wills to act "upon God, then it is not necessary to traverse any way in order to dis cover God, as though he had a definite position in space. The rather is the activity of God everywhere alike immediately and perfectly present, without dif ference of degree. Only this is meant by 'Omnipresence.' On the contrary, no one ever had any interest in ascribing positively to God himself, as one of his attributes, the predicate of an infinitely great extension in space. Quite the opposite, the simple design has been held of denying with reference to him in every respect that power to put under conditions which space-limitation exercises upon the recipro cal action of finite beings. THE PREDICATE OF OMNIPOTENCE. 49 • § 30. The predicate of Omnipotence obviously presupposes that conceptions of activity, either barely transforming or else creative, have some applicability to God ; and, under this presupposi tion, it is then sought to exalt the power of God absolutely above all bounds ; but in the ordinary conception of this attribute such a result is not obtained. The simplest interpretation of Omnipotence, that " God can do all possible," does not satisfy the religious feeling ; we should thus obtain only the relatively greatest one of those finite forces which, collectively, are obliged to acknowledge certain lim its of 'possibility' that stand fixed independently of them. God would therefore be subjected to a sphere of laws antecedent even to himself, which would determine for him the free scope of his power. The other explanation — " God can make even the impossible to be possible and actual" — without doubt expresses the real heart-meaning of the re ligious feeling, but, in the aforesaid way of formu lating it, appears absurd and unthinkable. For all order, all consistency and all coherency of the world appear to depend upon the limits between the possible and the impossible being absolutely im movable. If that which is of itself impossible can once be made possible by any power whatever, 5O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. then every sure foundation for making any conclu sion whatever in relation to the coherency of the world falls away. But even this last explanation does the very thing for which it finds fault with the first ; it assumes that this distinction of the impossible from the possible already exists independently of God. God finds them both already determined and authenticated by means of a truth that is independ ent of himself ; and only in practice does the ca pacity belong to him of withdrawing aught that is subordinated to the self-authenticated conception of the impossible, from the domain of this concep tion, and of disposing it under the conception of the possible. The thought mentioned above is neither sound in general, nor is such an omnipotence actually unlimited. Rather must we arrive at such an apprehension of God as makes God himself to be the prime reason for the opposition of the possible and the impossible having any significance at all in the world of actual existence. This thought, which is hard to define in the present connection, we shall pursue further later on. For our immediate purpose, that which is of religious value in it permits of being most simply and effectively expressed in the not quite correct THE PREDICATE OF ETERNITY. 51 form that " God can do even the impossible." This form at least states one thing clearly, — to wit, that the impossible is no barrier for God. § 31. The predicate of Eternity in time depends upon different motives ; first, as may be readily understood, upon the need that we be able to re gard what is to be our support and our consolation as at no time ready to fail. But then, apart from every religious need, eternal duration is aestheti cally an imposing idea on accotfht of a sublimity which is worthy of the Absolute Principle. But the aforesaid expression, nevertheless, does not itself depend upon our seeing any value or any advantage in the bare filling-up of infinite time. Just as we did not apprehend omnipresence as a positive magnitude in space, but only as the nega tion of all restrictive significations of space for the action of God; just so, 'infinite duration' signifies only the perfect independence of all those condi tions that change in time, by which finite beings are constantly confined within a definite tract of their possible existence. § 32. Moreover ' Time ' also, like Space, is not to be thought of as though it were a somehow self-existing form, and as though God had only 52 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. the capacity of filling it up by his existence, how ever far it may extend. But the difficult at tempts which have been made to apprehend this relation otherwise, — to consider time as in God, or God as above time, — we must defer pro visionally and make prominent another point in stead. God, as filling eternal time in a perfectly un changeable way, would be a mental representation of no service for religious interests. But if God is living and the subject of change, — that is, if anything whatever takes place within him, then it follows that he is in every second instant an other than he was in the first instant preceding ; — unless it can be demonstrated on other grounds in what way that ' Unity ' of his Being which is for us indispensable is maintained continuously through the course of his changes in time. Now, at this point we derive from Metaphysic the conviction that such ' Unity of a Being with itself ' certainly presupposes all its successive states to be comprehensible as different consequences of one and the same nature, and — in brief — to cohere together in accordance with one and the same formula ; but, likewise, the conviction that this presupposition is not at all adequate. For if we also, the thinking subjects, in the series of states a, o.lt «,, 03, . . ., every- THE UNITY OF SELF-CONSCIOUS SPIRIT. 53 where observe the secondary effect of the original nature a of a being ; and if we, on this account, apprehend such a series as the history of one and the same being a : still it is in this way by no means yet proved, that this is more than a subjec tive apprehension on our part ; — that is to say, that the a, a1( 02, . . ., are not different successive beings instead of only successive states of one and the same Being (a). If the latter conclusion is to be proved,' then only the Being a itself can prove it ; and, of course, only by itself doing what, previously, merely we, the investigating subjects, have done. The Being a must comprehend itself as a ' unity ' ; must, as such, set itself over against the series a, 04, . . ., as mere states of its own, and be able to unite these successive states into one synchronous state by means of recollection. Expressed in simple man ner : In no respect can we assert of selfless ' Things,' but only of a self-conscious ' Spirit,' that it remains in the course of its history one and the same ; and, for the very reason that only it actual izes the aforesaid unity by means of this deed of self-consciousness. Of a 'Thing,' on the contrary, — since it is merely subject to different states one after another, although in a sequence according 54 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. to law, — there is no decisive test by which to prove the fact and the means of its distinguishing itself from a succession of different and merely related Things. CHAPTER IV. OF THE PERSONALITY OF THE ABSOLUTE. § 33. The paradoxical result of the previous re flections is as follows : If all the predicates of 'unconditionateness' are to be valid for the Highest Being, then one condition of this validity lies pre cisely in the addition of a last formal predicate, — namely, that of Personal Existence. At the faith in this ' personality of God ' the religious faculty, naturally enough, has not arrived by the above-mentioned way, but from familiar motives that lie nearer at hand. Against this faith, however, philosophic reflection has subse quently been very unanimously directed with the assertion: 'Personality' is conceivable only in finite spirits, and in this case rests on conditions which can have no significance for the Absolute. The above-mentioned investigations concerning the possibility or impossibility of the assumption of a ' personal God ' should be briefly repeated in this connection. § 34. Two thoughts which we believe ourselves obliged to distinguish, lie in the conception of 'per sonality.' 56 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. First: No 'personality/ or — what can for the moment pass as identical with it — no ' self-con sciousness' is conceivable without our ascribing to the spiritual subject, to which it is to belong, an image of cognition or an image of representation, of that which this subject itself is, and by means of which it distinguishes itself from others. Since these images of cognition, as well as those which we project for ourselves from other objects, may be more or less either correct or false ; therefore, self-consciousness is by no means identical with 'adequate self-cognition.' We are rather to esti mate the different degrees of its clearness and per fection exactly according to the measure of the conformity of its content with the actual nature of the subject. But the mental representation of the aforesaid pic ture will always deserve the title of 'self-conscious ness ' so long as it contains this second factor : — to wit, so long as the other additional thought is present, that this mental image is the image of ourselves, and is by no means distinguished from any other image merely in the same way that a second object is distinguished from a third; but that it is rather significant of somewhat which, as 'ego,' is to be placed in a fundamental and incom parable opposition to all else. This second trans action we consider in the first place. DEVELOPMENT OF SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS. 57 § 35. It is a very common opinion that ' self-con sciousness ' is a spiritual phenomenon which develops very gradually, and the origin and necessary con ditions of which, accordingly, have a history. Such an opinion we recognize as correct only in relation to the first of the points distinguished above. To wit : We doubtless do not arrive at the knowledge of the properties of which we compose the before-mentioned mental image, or at the con tent of the image of ourselves which we construct for ourselves, except by means of an accumulation of external and internal experiences. But in relation to the other point we cannot assent to this opinion. It does not admit of being shown intelligibly, how, in the course of the pro jection of manifold mental representations, the moment must necessarily at some time arrive, when we should be compelled to consider one of these representations, not merely as image of one object which is distinguished from a second only in the same way as the latter from a third, but precisely as the image of our 'ego,' which stands in that absolute opposition to every non-ego, so easily in telligible but so difficult further to describe. It will be found that the apparent ' origin ' of self-consciousness in this sense always presupposes the latent previous existence of its most essential 58 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. element, — namely, of a self-feeling in the same sense. § 36. The materialistic attempts to generate self- consciousness from all manner of motions in brain- atoms returning upon themselves, are deserving of no respect. As they are unable in general to de duce any ' consciousness ' from motions, so is this return of the motions also unable to generate any .^^consciousness. But, on the whole, the frequent philosophical assertions — Personality can only be generated by an activity of the ego proceeding outward, and by a resistance of the non-ego which ' reflects ' this 'activity upon its own point of issue — are not a whit better. These modes of speech correspond to absolutely no demonstrable and real transaction. Such an activity of the ego proceeding outward nowhere admits of being designated by name. The analogy that it is thrown back like rays of light from the non-ego, is a mental image utterly without real motif, and one under which it is not possible to bring any actual procedure. The con clusion finally, that this activity becomes ' self-con sciousness ' by means of such ' reflection,' is a bare subreption. For it is precisely by this means that the mere return of the activity to its own point of THE IDEA OF THE EGO. 59 issue is occasioned. But that it should now be compelled to apprehend this point as its own self, — and hence the precise origin of self-conscious ness, — is a mere supplement of thought devoid of all basis. Only those attempts would deserve consideration which aim to show how the soul originally pro duces merely intuitive ideas, and then, in the course of the reciprocal actions of these its individual products, projects also conceptions of non-intuitive subjects to which the aforesaid ideas belong as predicates ; that it finally succeeds also in assign ing by thought one subject to the totality of all its inner states ; and that it thus generates the consciousness of the ' ego ' as of that one which is at the same time subject and object of the act of ideation. § 37. It is to be alleged, in the first place, against such attempts as the foregoing, that identity of ideating subject and ideated object is the general notion of every personality ; and that, therefore, ' I ' is not by this means distinguishable from ' thou ' and 'he.' And yet ' self -consciousness ' or 'person ality ' obviously does not consist in subsuming ourselves, together with all others under one and the same general notion : but it consists in our 6O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. distinguishing ourselves from all others within this general notion. It might now be said : ' I ' am subject and ob ject of my thoughts, 'thou' art subject and object of thine, etc. If distinguishing thus is not to bring us round and round in a constant circle, then the distinction between 'mine' and 'thine' — the one we need to make — cannot be deduced from the fact that the ' mine ' belongs to the ' I,' and the ' thine ' to the ' thou ' ; but between both of them there must already exist a distinction that is abso lutely clear, immediately given, and in need of no deduction at all. Such now is actually the case ; and the distinc tion depends upon this, that we are in general unable to think of any soul exclusively as a being active merely in the formation of ideas. Every soul is rather likewise capable of experiencing feelings of pleasure and of pain, and of combining these feelings with the content of ideas. Simply by means of the fact that the idea of any state whatsoever is combined with a feeling of pleasure or pain, is such state authenticated as our own, and no longer passes merely as the state of some being or other. We express the matter simply by means of the following antithesis : Granted that some superior FEELING AND SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS. 6 1 spirit possesses so perfect an intelligence as to have a quite adequate cognition of all things, and of its own being as well, and yet is utterly lack ing in the faculty for pleasure and pain ; and that every conceivable content is therefore as indif ferent to it as is every other. Then such a spirit will not merely cognize itself, but will also know that in this case the cognizing subject is identical with the object cognized. It will, however, at the same time cognize the fact, that the case of such identity may occur precisely so millions of times in other beings ; and it will have no motive at all to regard one of these cases — just that one which occurs in its own self — as something special, and to distinguish this case from those others ; it will not, therefore, apprehend itself as an 'ego' set over against some other as the 'non-ego.' On the other hand, an animal of the lowest order, that has scarcely any cognition of itself at all, but has indeed feeling for pleasure and pain, will never confound itself with the external world. When it feels a smart, it will experience this state as one belonging to itself alone ; and just by this means will it feel itself as an 'ego' in opposition to the whole world, although it would not know at all how to specify precisely in what its own being consists. 62 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. § 38. We arrive at the same goal by another way. We often hear it said : ' Ego ' and ' non- ego ' are two correlative conceptions, neither of which has in general any significance apart from its opposition to the other. Therefore, — it is said, — even the idea of the ' ego ' can originate only at the moment when that of the ' non-ego ' likewise originates. On this account, 'personality' is pos sible only for finite beings which can be limited by a non-ego. The foregoing three propositions have really no inner connection with each other. The first of them must be pronounced perfectly absurd. Two conceptions, each of which should have a meaning only as a negation of the other, and should signify nothing further, would both of them have no mean ing at all, and would not even acquire any by their being opposed to each other. One of the two must necessarily be independently determined and signify something. On consideration of our case we find the ques tion to be : If ' ego ' and ' non-ego ' were two such conceptions, each of which contained barely the negation of the other : by what means would the soul then be induced, at the moment of the simultaneous origin of both, to rank itself under the conception of the ' ego ' rather than under that THE TERM ' NON-EGO ' RELATIVE. 63 of the ' non-ego ' ; and what does it gain thereby if it does the one and forbears the other ? To such a question no answer is possible but just this ; that one of the two conceptions signifies some what independently determined, and on this ac count the spirit applies it to itself, or does not so apply it. Now, without going further, the expres sions themselves show that this independent sig nificance belongs only to the ' ego ' as positively apprehended. What is meant by the term is directly obvious : what, on the contrary, is meant by the negative expression ' non-ego ' is in a pre liminary way obscure ; and only thus much is known about it, — namely, that it is not the 'ego.' But this is just what would be achieved by the aforesaid immediate feeling, by which the ego posi tively apprehends what belongs to it as its own; and, on the other hand, at first excludes from 'itself in a merely negative way what does not belong to it. § 39. The above position being conceded, it is still always possible to say : This ' feeling of the ego,' although in itself of a definite content, which does not primarily originate by means of its op position to the non-ego, nevertheless, as a matter of fact, cannot actually occur except at the moment 64 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. of such an opposition. To see colors is also an original capacity of the soul, and could not be pro cured for it by means of any waves of ether, if it did not of itself possess the capacity ; yet we do see colors solely in case waves of ether act on us. Just so we feel ourselves as 'ego,' only in case an opposed non-ego acts on us. On this point it is now to be observed, that the possibility of personality is in any case erroneously attached to the opposition to a real non-ego ; as though by means of it that being, which in conse quence thereof then feels itself as 'ego,' became really limited. A reciprocal action with a real non-ego, of such kind that this as such might enter into consciousness and the ego thus be posited in opposition to this per ceived non-ego, never occurs at all. In all sensations and perceptions, what enters consciousness in con sequence of such an influence, is invariably nothing but some inner state belonging to the spiritual being, — the sensation or mental representation it self ; it is never the reality by means of which the state is brought about. From these inner states the entire subsequent development of the spiritual life, and therefore that of the personality, proceeds. It suffices for laying the foundation of the latter, if a spiritual being has THE EXCITATION OF THE EGO. 6$ the faculty of apprehending itself as 'I' in opposi tion to its own states, which are only its 'states' and not 'I.' A relation to an external reality is not necessary ; and, consequently, ' personality ' also is not bound to the condition of finiteness, — to wit, to that of being limited by another reality of the same kind. § 40. It may nevertheless always be said: Even if, in a course of thought that is once in process, this world of thoughts can serve as the non-ego in opposition to which the thinking spirit knows itself as the ego, still the first excitation of such process of thought needs the influence from without which can only be given by an actual reality affect ing the senses. But this objection unwarrantably carries over what takes place as a matter of fact in the case of us men, as though it were indispen sable to every personality. In all attempts at a physical explanation of the world, we are at last under the necessity of recog nizing, not merely certain real elements, but also certain motions of the same, as original data; and it is of no advantage to search further for the causes of these motions also, — since they could only consist of still other motions ; nor is it con ceivable how we are ever to get from a state of 66 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. equilibrium or rest as originally assumed, to dis turbance of equilibrium or to motion. Only the same concession, and no more, is re quired in relation to the Infinite Spirit. It is not to be thought of as somewhat which it were barely possible to imagine, but as somewhat which is im agined as eternally and unceasingly actual ; — some what to which no such state ' of rest was ever antecedent, as a state from which it would have been obliged to be extricated by means of special influence. § 41. All further inquiries concerning this mat ter (as to what, perhaps, gives conditions to this eternal movement of thought with respect to its content and its direction) must, of course, remain unanswered. Nevertheless it can be shown — not, indeed, with a strictness that satisfies the demands of science, but still in a manner intelligible to imagination, — why the matter stands with us men in that different fashion which we should not be justified in wanting to carry over and apply to God. When treating of ' Omnipresence ' allusion was made to the truth, that God, who is the truly Existent in all Things and comprises them all as mere modifications of his Being, stands in need of FINITE SPIRITS DEPEND ON THINGS. 6/ no mediation through transmitted effects, in order to be acquainted with the individual elements of the world and the states belonging to them. Every finite spirit, however, has its existence only from a definite point of time onward, and has in the coherence of all Things a determinate position in the system, which assigns to it also a limited place in space. Now it follows from the above-mentioned truth, that finite spirits, who have very much outside of themselves which they themselves are not, stand in absolute need of a real outside world and of its effects, in order to attain to the development of the life of thought possible to them. It is intelligible, further, that finite spirits who are not the Absolute itself but only modifications or fragments of the same, and yet likewise possess all their existence only through this Absolute, do constantly, in case they reflect upon themselves, suppose that they find an obscure germ in their own being, — to wit, just this power of the Absolute itself. This power it is which works through and through them, and, without their own assistance, prescribes for them the universal forms of their spiritual activity, their sensation, imagination, judg ment, etc. ; and which permits them only within nar row limits to dispose further of this dowry, and 68 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. to pursue their special ends. That is to say, therefore : ' Personality ' is in them only very im perfectly accomplished. There remains something back in the ego, which it cannot itself explain. This is a fact which is corroborated by the course of Psychology, wherein always at last the question recurs, — What then really are we ? and can never be answered to our perfect satisfaction. Finally, it does not indeed admit of direct proof, but is none the less a probable assumption, that the laws of the psychical mechanism to which our inner life is subjected are also connected with this 'finiteness.' From them it follows, however, that our ideas inhibit one another ; that only a small number of them is at any time present in con sciousness ; that the forgotten ones return, indeed, to our recollection in accordance with general laws, but not always in a manner corresponding to our momentary need. Hence it comes about that we frequently over-hasten ; that we permit certain measures of conception which are just present in consciousness, partially to pass over into transac tions which we later, when we have collected our selves, may no longer recognize as our own ; that, finally, we forget very much, and with increasing age can no longer transport ourselves back into the frames of mind, feelings and enthusiasms of the earlier epochs of life. THE INFINITE A PERFECT PERSONALITY. 69 All these hindrances of a perfect ' personality ' we can imagine as not existent in the Infinite Spirit. On this account, we conclude with the assertion which is exactly the opposite of the customary one : Perfect personality is reconcilable only with the conception of an Infinite Being ; for finite beings only an approximation to this is at tainable. CHAPTER V. OF THE CONCEPTION OF CREATION. § 42. We reserve the further concrete predi cates, chiefly of an ethical kind, by which we have to complete the still abstract conception of an infinite personality, until after we have consid ered the relation of this personality to the world. And this relation itself we treat for convenience under the three distinctive names of Creation, Preservation and Government. In relation to the first topic, we omit all ancient and modern cosmogonies, such as intend to fur nish an intuitive picture of the process of 'crea tion ' and of the succession of particular creative acts ; — a picture, which is in general impossible, and in particulars not to be established with any certainty. Our design is merely to show what fundamental conceptions admit of being formed concerning that relation of God to the world from which the creation proceeds, or in which it consists, or which is established by means of it. We divide the essentially different views, which are possible on this subject, into the three fol lowing : the first of which attempts to trace the CREATION NOT DEVELOPMENT. 71 world to the "consistent development of the nature of God," the second to his will, the third to a creative act. § 43. The first view, crudely elaborated and satisfying merely to the imagination but not to speculation, appears in all the emanation theories of ancient and modern times. This we exclude from our investigation. On the contrary, the conception of the world as a 'necessary, involuntary, and inevitable devel opment of the nature of God,' which rests essen tially upon the foundation of modern scientific views, is worthy of consideration. So far as this view endeavors to exclude a God who rules without principle in blind arbitrariness, it is correct ; and in this respect corresponds also to our religious need. But we must resist with the greatest possible decisiveness the further apotheosis of the notion of ' development ' conse quent upon this view, which it is customary just now to express and to extol with such great em phasis, as though it were identical, as a matter of course, with all that is great and sublime and holy. If it were only a question concerning a theo retic explanation of the course of the world, then such a conception would be satisfactory. But it 72 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. is wholly useless from the religious point of view, because it leads consistently to nothing but a thorough-going Determinism, according to which not only is every thing that must happen, in case certain conditions occur, appointed in pursuance of general laws ; but according to which even the suc cessive occurrence of these conditions, and conse quently the whole of history with all its details, is predetermined. In such a mechanical contrivance there is no place whatever for any 'freedom' or 'activity,' or for an effort that shall produce aught which does not originate from the mechanism itself. Religious opinion assumes rather that, while there are uni versal laws, without whose efficacy no ' design ' whatever would be able by definite means to attain to a definite goal, there is however at the same time, on the basis and in the domain of this reign of law, a free, voluntary activity, which, by the use and combination of the given elements acting in accordance with law, produces that even, which would have no existence without such activity. The above-mentioned assumption has its diffi culties. Until, however, it is shown decisively to be impossible, the religious feeling will never re turn to the thought of an ' undesigned, inevitable development ' of the world from the nature of God, CREATIVE WILL NOT MOMENTARY. 73 but will derive it from an act of the divine will, without which it would not have existed. § 44. In speaking of the will of God, we natu rally think first of the analogy of our own will ; we may not however summarily transfer to the former that which is peculiar to the latter. Now the aims to which our will can be directed, are only given to us finite beings progressively by means of experience. Hence under the term * will ' we conceive primarily of a spiritual activity momentarily awakening, which is directed chiefly to the production of a state not yet existing, or to the change of a state already existing. Even in those cases in which we ' will ' nothing new but merely the status quo, we become conscious of this act of will, at least distinctly so, only if something threatens to disturb this state that has been ' willed ' by us. The foregoing conceptions are not applicable to the creative will of God. Although the imagi nation naturally represents the dependence of the world upon the will of God in the most forcible manner by making a period of time precede in which even this creative will of God had no existence ; still there is no ground whatever for forming a philosophical tenet out of this view, 74 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. — harmless as it is to religion, — and for speaking of an inner life in God, which, after this period, has proceeded to the decision to create and to its execution. Besides it would be impossible to fill this space of time with anything but a delusive history of development, in which the systematic coherence of all the thoughts, by uniting which we endeavor to interpret for ourselves the being of God, would be fictitiously converted into a chro nological sequence ; and by this means the nature of God would for the first time become completely realized. This is, philosophically considered, erroneous, and religiously devoid of all significance : we abide therefore by the assumption, that the 'will to create' is an absolutely eternal predicate of God, and ought not to be used to designate a deed of his so much as the absolute dependence of the world upon his will in contradistinction to its in voluntary ' emanation ' from his nature. § 45. With the foregoing assertion, however, there seems to vanish something which we regard as necessary for the religious conception of crea tion ; to wit, a will which is constantly existent, has no longer the character of a deed. In order that will may be distinguished from that involuntary WILLING CONSIDERED AS DEED. 75 development, from which we intended to distin guish it, it seems necessary that some deed or work be added to the act of will, by whose accom plishment alone that which is willed truly becomes the complete possession of the one who wills, and at the same time becomes a reality. There is in volved herein an undoubtedly genuine religious need, but it is wrongly formulated in dependence upon analogies derived from our own willing and doing, which are not transferable to God. In the first place as regards the efficacy of our own will, we know psychologically that our 'will- ing ' can never do anything else but produce a definite psychical state within us (an idea, a feel ing, a wish). With this state, as soon as it is once in existence, an order of nature under the control of general law, wholly independent of our volition and hardly accessible to our intelligence, has connected a definite result ; and this result then originates without our being able to compre hend the process of its origination or to con tribute anything further to it. Now we believe to be sure that, in the performance of our corporal movements, we feel at once the transition of our will to the limbs, and that to a certain extent we observe the will at its work, by which it brings to pass the 76 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. effect. But it is known psychologically, that we actually feel in this case only the changes, which the will, in a manner wholly beyond the power of observation, has already produced in the limbs, and from which, in a supplemental way, the sen sations of weariness and exertion are produced in the consciousness. These feelings therefore do not show us how those movements are produced by us ; but they only show how much disturbance our organism has experienced, in consequence of those movements having been attached to the action of our will, in accordance with an order of nature unknown to us. If therefore we recognize as our own ' deed ' an effect which issues from us only in case we have had, at the time of its accomplishment, all the aforesaid feelings, then this analogy of the human will cannot be transferred to God. For this apparent activity in accomplishing something beyond the bare action of willing is in truth merely a witness to the powerlessness of our will, which effects something only in case a higher power has united with it the origination of changes in external objects. In this sense, therefore, we may not, in addi tion to the creative will of God, still further postulate a special creative deed ; but we must REALIZATION OF THE DIVINE WILL. fj be satisfied with the thought that the will of the Supreme Being is without further procedure the realization of that which He wills. § 46. But after all there remains a genuine religious need, which was expressed, although wrongly, by the demand for a divine work of creation. The value of the feelings, to which we referred, does not consist in the fact that they brought to our view the modus agendi of our will, but that at each minutest instant they furnished us the knowl edge as to how far the realization of its activity had already advanced. Suppose, for example, that we give our arm a wide swing, then we have at each minutest point of time a new sensation which discloses to us the magnitude of the breadth of the movement already executed ; and therefore the progress of our wills' mode of operation, although in itself unobserved, is noted by us from the beginning to the end of the move ment. Now it is precisely because in such a case our consciousness always has an immediate feeling in conjunction with the product of the will, that such movements appear as, in the strict est sense, our own living deed. On the contrary, in the case of the stone that flies away from the PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. hand at the completion of that movement of the arm, although it has in fact got its velocity by means of us, still we have no immediate sensation of its further movement. While this movement, therefore, as well as its subsequent effects upon other objects, seem to us to be consequences of our deed, they no longer seem to be our own ac tivity itself. Now it is the counterpart of just this, which it is really intended to exclude from the concep tion of the divine creative work. It is not to be supposed that the act of will originates a bare result in which the consciousness of the one who wills were no longer present ; but it is to be sup posed that the creative will remains in that con stant feeling in conjunction with the state of its product, which we men experience only on occasion of the movements of our own body, and not on occasion of the movements of external objects in directly produced. Now because this feeling in our case is psycho logically connected with the effort and labor, which are simply a consequence of our finite nature, some have arrived at the false conception that this must be so even in the case of God Himself; and on this account have demanded the aforesaid special work of creation. NO PROCESS OF CREATION. 79 § 47. The sum and substance of the preceding discussion is, that the conception of creation prop erly signifies nothing more than this ; that the world, with respect to its existence as well as its content, is completely dependent upon the will of God, and not a mere involuntary ' development ' of his nature ; that it proceeds, however, only from the will and not from a special work of God, — this latter conception being always applicable only in cases where a will endeavors to realize its pur pose in conflict with an existing world that is independent of it : whereas of God we in fact assert that He " has created the world out of nothing," — a strange expression, which strictly interpreted means to say, in a merely negative manner, that there is nothing out of which God constructed the world ; and which then whimsi cally makes this Nothing appear again as a sort of 'stuff' from which it is created. • There can be no consistent description of the process of creation, for the reason that there is no such process. Such process in fact, whenever the attempt has been made to imagine it, has always presupposed in turn the existence of another world, and of certain forms of happening already in use in it. In regard still further to the content of crea- 8O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. tion, it would be from a religious 'point of view an object of interest for us, only in case we con ceive withal of a plan which is to be realized in the world ; and this subject is to be discussed under the head of the conception of 'Government.' CHAPTER VI. OF PRESERVATION. § 48. To ascribe the preservation of the world to a special divine activity, may seem to be a super fluous thought. In fact, the common opinion of natural philosophy amounts to this, that the world, when once in existence, maintains itself as a mat ter of course by the efficacy of the laws which have once gained prevalence in it. The utmost that is conceded is, that the origination of the world may be the object of an action, but not its continuation after it has once originated. The foregoing opinion only serves to remind us that we really have already before us, even with re spect to creation, a difficulty of which, in the ordi nary reflection, we are less sensible only in relation to this conception of preservation. To wit, the ques tion is raised, in what way God, in the action of his will, has arrived at a decision concerning that which should be or should not be. The readiest answer, — namely that He has summoned into actual existence only that which is in itself possible, — as well as the other answer, — that He has summoned into actual 82 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. existence the best among many possible worlds, both contain the thought that what is good or not good, possible or not possible, has already been decided independently of the will of God ; and therefore that, after all, there precedes God, the Supreme Principle, a certain realm of eternal truths as a still higher Principle, to which He together with his activity is now obliged to become subordinate. This strange idea is not improved by the immediate reply that, in the use of a distinction frequently made, we designate those ' eternal truths ' merely as the ' content of God's under standing,' and not as a necessity foreign to Him and which stands over against Him objectively. No improvement of the idea is attained so long at least as we have in mind in this connection our own spiritual life, in which of course all these general truths appear as something pro ceeding from a higher power and not connected with our personality ; or, at all events, as some thing not deducible from it. Concerning these difficulties we must make the following somewhat detailed reflections. § 49. It has already been observed, in dis coursing of the possibility of the reciprocal LAWS NOT INDEPENDENT OF GOD. 83 actions of the elements of the world, that the prevalent method of speaking of the "authority of general laws of nature over Things " has noth ing properly corresponding to it in the actual state of the case. Laws can exist only in a twofold manner : they may either exist at the instant when they are obeyed, as the activity of the elements them selves, which seem to follow them ; or, in the observing spirits which compare the events, as conscious rules for the combination of the ideas, by which we (the observing spirits) are enabled, in accordance with the reality, to determine beforehand from given states those which suc ceed them. On the contrary, laws never exist outside, between, beside, or above the Things that are to obey them. And if we ourselves should intend to assume that a ghost-like existence, of a sort that is wholly beyond the power of representation, belongs to them, the question would be left the more un answerable, how in that case they went to work to secure obedience from the elements which were wholly foreign to them. This first mode of representation, then, accord ing to which God even would have 'found at hand ' a sum of self-existing truths, must be wholly abandoned. 84 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. § 50. The first modification of the thought we are considering, to the effect that the eternal truths were nothing else but the mode of the action of God's own nature and intelligence, we found, just at the close of the last paragraph but one, to be not altogether satisfactory. To wit : we find in ourselves such truths (as for example the law of identity, or the simple geometrical intuitions, or the fundamental ethical judgments of our conscience), as do not present themselves to us, at any rate when considered individually, as something foreign to our nature, but as the mode of our own experience or the form of our own activity. But we find several of such truths within us, and we find no connection between them. For, from the fact that the propo sition of identity is a necessity of our thought, it by no means certainly follows that we must also have an intuition of space, or must make a distinc tion between good and evil. Hence the aggregate of these truths seems to us after all to be some thing foreign to our own being, and not deducible from it; or at least something whose origin from it cannot be known. If it were thus with God, it would seem to us as if He met with these eternal truths, not to be sure as forces external to Himself, but as some- ETERNAL TRUTHS DO NOT LIMIT GOD. 85 thing within Himself, which He could regard only in the light of a gift bestowed upon Him as it were. Now we can of course never give a positive de scription of the manner in which those truths, that to our discernment are disparate, are united with each other in God, and are experienced as belong ing together in the unity of a single thought. But, for all that, there is no contradiction in the as sumption that with God it is so ; and that only we finite beings, who are able to possess nothing but fragments of the whole of truth, fail to grasp the inner connection by which these truths are perfected into one whole. § 51. The above-mentioned view of the case also often proves unsatisfactory. The assumption, that the eternal truths are the proper modus agendi of the divine understanding itself, has always seemed to many to involve after all a limitation of his un- conditionateness and omnipotence. In such case we should not be content with anything less than the statement that God did not possess this modus agendi, but that He first bestowed it upon Himself. Indeed even in such case it might perhaps still be doubted, whether in the choice of such a modus from among many that are conceivable and now 86 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. excluded, there were not after all again involved a limitation of his unconditionateness, although a self-chosen limitation. In one view of the matter, however, it may be remarked that in this way the conception of God loses all content whatever ; and that, instead of conceiving of that concrete Being to whom uncon ditionateness in respect to his conduct belongs, we have made the empty conception of uncondi tionateness itself the subject or the principle of the world. To do this is, fundamentally consid ered, just the same mistake that is made when we content ourselves with the abstract expressions, the ' One,' the ' Existent,' the ' Absolute,' etc., and suppose that by them we have expressed the Su preme Principle, instead of designating by name or representing that which deserves to be acknowledged as the Real Principle of the world, because it pos sesses in virtue of its own concrete nature the alleged predicates. But the misunderstandings that arise in this con nection admit of being analyzed somewhat further in detail. § 52. If, in the first place, we see a limitation of omnipotence in the fact, that even omnipotence, from its very beginning onward, follows a definite CAPACITY NEVER INDETERMINATE. 8/ modus agcndi, then we may in the next place be reminded that we in fact never mentally represent even any finite 'power' or 'capacity' as a predicate which would inhere in a Thing without connection with its remaining 11 predicates as an (n+l)th. Just as little do we represent such a power as a ' being- able in general,' which would still have no direction whatever ; so that it would only be de termined subsequently by secondary circumstances, what sort of activity this ' being able ' will exercise, and with reference to what objects. On the contrary every ' power ' or ' capacity ' is conceivable only as one that is quite definitely fixed in reality. And the abstract conpeption of 'capacity in general,' which we may form just as legitimately as the conception of ' motion in gen eral,' can just as little signify something real as can the latter before it is again furnished with a ' direc tion ' and a 'velocity,' from which, in the forma tion of the general conception, the abstraction was made. If now this conception of 'power' is to be ex alted to that of 'omnipotence,' it cannot be ac complished by omitting every such act of determi nation as would fix some modus agendi ; but only by representing just this modus as one so compre hensive, that all actual capacities and powers PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. whatever, which appear in the world, originate from it. In that, we should have substituted the mere general conception of power for the supreme actual Power. But still further, omnipotence, even in this case, cannot be conceived_of as a predicate addi tional to the rest of the predicates of God ; but it is only an expression for the efficacy in action of just these predicates, and therefore of that concrete nature of God in which all reality is comprehended. § 53. We may now be tempted for the last time to inquire : If God's omnipotence is only co-exten sive with his nature, why then has God -this de terminate nature a and not another b or c? and does not the fact that He is not this b or c involve again a limitation of his being ? In support of such thoughts an appeal is also made perhaps to the celebrated proposition " Omnis determinatio est negatio" ; the meaning of which is often enough thought to be, that all determination is limitation, because it is the product of the nega tion of innumerable other possibilities. Thus understood, the proposition would be thoroughly false. It is only in cases where a com pletely disjunctive judgment is already validated, in accordance with which a subject s must be either a or b or c, that the affirmation of a can NEGATION AND AFFIRMATION. 89 originate from the negation of b and c. And even in such cases this negation ia» nothing more than a reason for our cognition, from which we conclude that s is a, but is not a reason in reality why s is actually a. That is to say ; It is not the real de termination, but our subjective certainty of its existence, that follows from the negation of other possibilities. But in other cases, as a rule, the above-men tioned proposition can only signify, not that every determination originates from a negation of that which is different from it, but that it is accessory to, or consequent upon, such negation. If we thus apprehend the proposition, the doubt above suggested will subside ; the doubt, namely, whether after all there is not again involved a limi tation of a, in the very fact that something can now no longer be b or c, because it is originally a. This thought has some significance for us finite beings, to whom a determinate nature a is given, beside and outside of which the natures p and -y of other beings — as for example those of other species of animals — are likewise met with as actualities. Since then we are unable to transpose ourselves out of our own nature into the p and -y foreign to us, this incapacity seems to us a limitation which prevents our enjoyment of a good that actually exists. QO PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. But the foregoing analogy is not transferable to the nature of God. For this nature a is pre cisely such an one as is not the product of a still higher nature M, among the consequences of which it would find itself coordinated with the other equally real products b and c : and at the same time excluded from them. But out side of this a nothing exists : a is rather the primal source of the sum-total of reality ; and, indeed, a source of such sort that, owing to its concrete nature, thinking beings also are met with in this realm of reality, who are able to distinguish a from a never-existent, but con ceivable non-a ; and who now are able to raise the wondrous question, why all the world bears the character of this a and not the other char acter of a non-a. The noteworthy capacity for denying in thought what actually exists, — a capacity which is itself only a product of the laws that are valid in actuality upon the basis of that a, — misleads us into the acceptance of this strange and utterly unthinkable idea : before God was and before the world was, there was already a multitude of coor dinate, possible future Gods and worlds ; and there was possible and necessary a choice between them, by which the total character a of the actual God, GOD AND ETERNAL TRUTH. 91 and of the actual World was established ; but at the same time there was by this means intro duced a limitation of both of them, because now they could no longer be b and c. § 54. We arrive at the same result, if we undertake to think through one of the two fol lowing propositions : ' God has only recognized the truth ' ; or, 'He has created it.' Arbitrary statutes admit of being ' recognized ' in so far as our transactions are willingly or reluctantly accommodated to them. But in thinking we can only ' recognize ' as truth that which accords with the laws of such thinking, — that is, with its modus agendi. And thus even God would have been able to ' recognize ' any ' truth ' that he met with, as truth, only because it had already belonged to the intrinsic nature of his own thought. Moreover statutes of all sorts admit of being 'made,' and a practical obedience to them may be enforced : but to make something which, after it is done, should constitute a truth, is only possible in case the productive energy itself is already of itself fulfilling, as rules of its own action, precisely the same conditions as those that are conditions of the truth to the intelligence associated with the energy. PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. By both paths, then, we return to the propo sition, that eternal truths are neither antecedent norms nor subsequent products of the divine activ ity ; but are nothing else than the actual form of this very energizing ; and that, in the special sense of the word ' truth/ they appear as com mands, which something not yet existent must satisfy, only in our subjective reflection, in case we attempt to bring the future into combination with the present. § 55. The foregoing considerations are con nected with the conception of the Preservation of the world in the following manner. The common view of nature, in modern times, either asserts that God indeed created the world at the beginning, but after it was created left it to itself and to the further development of the general laws which He established in it. Or, in the other case, since the act of creation can never be made apprehensible, such act is entirely left out ; and it is simply asserted that the world which lies ready-made before us, is maintained by the constant prevalence of its general laws, and needs no divine support. In opposition to this the proposition of religion is heard : " Preservation is continual new-creation." SUBSTANCE AS INDESTRUCTIBLE. 93 It is not conceivable that this can be intended to mean : The world of the next instant is, as to its content, entirely new and foreign to that of the preceding instant. So far from this, we naturally accept the assumption that, in the divine activity, there is unity and coherence ; and, for this reason, the creative act of the next instant also is a consequence of that of the preceding. But, nevertheless, the aforesaid proposition would deny that the world of one instant perpetuates itself by its own agency and by its general laws into the next instant. For that very reason it will be superfluous, as regards all special inquiries into the coherence of the processes of nature, to come back to the 'co- working of God ' ; and it is sufficient to speak of the consecutive order of nature which He has established. Still, in our idea of the whole, we must decidedly guard against the view which speaks of an actual self-sufficiency of nature, and which, from this as from a secure stand-point, exercises a negative criticism in opposition to the religious in tuitions. It must rather be asserted that if corporal 'sub stance ' is indestructible, it is not so by its own agency or in accordance with a claim to the right growing out of its own nature, but because the 94 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. divine creative power preserves it continuously at each instant ; and that if, in the course of nature, the Same forces always act according to the same laws, this does not come to pass because these forces were of themselves eternal and these laws of themselves efficient, but because it lies within the plan of the divine efficiency to employ, at each instant of the course of the world, this number of homogeneous actions, as means for the production of more composite products. In a word : The entire interior consistency of the cohering order of nature, upon which the natural sciences are supported, is conceded as a matter of fact ; but taken as a whole and at large it is regarded as a system of mutually condition ing actualities, utterly dependent upon the divine power ; so that ultimately, therefore, the World does not preserve itself but is preserved by God. CHAPTER VII. OF GOVERNMENT. § 56. We can only speak of Government in case there' are elements that, with a certain inde pendence of behavior on their part, threaten to withdraw from a plan prescribed to them, which the governing principle intends to realize. The considerations to which we last referred therefore seem to leave no place for the application of this conception. Indeed, in proportion as these considerations themselves make the preservation of the world dependent upon the constant action of the will of God, do they obscure the thought to which we would firmly hold; — namely, that the World is not a mere immanent development of God, but a product of his will. In order that this contradiction may have any significance, the product of the will, after it is created, would have to possess a certain independ ence. Or, to use a well-known mode of expres sion, the world would have to be 'outside' of God and not merely a process 'in' Him. We need not adhere to these last mentioned expressions in terms of space which would lead 96 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. to such endless and perfectly empty disputes ; but the inquiry must be made as to what must really' constitute that 'mode of behavior' which it is sup posed may be figuratively designated by these expressions. And to this question the only answer will probably be, that only that Reality possesses the independence obviously here intended, which is able to have its own states, — such, that is, as are not immediately states of the ' Universal Sub stance ' ; and to initiate processes which do not proceed from that Substance. If now we consider how these abstract postulates might be fulfilled, we find but one Reality which actually fulfils them ; namely, spiritual life. A being which has experience of itself as an individual subject for its own states, and which distinguishes these states from those of other beings, may, it is true, be nothing whatever as to its entire existence but a product of the Infinite Being. But after it is once in existence, it is, by the very form of its existence, by this conscious ness which places itself in relation to itself, dis tinguished as an individual ego from the very Absolute, that in reality conditions it, and that now, as posited over against itself, belongs to the non-ego. And by this act, or by this form of its existence, does it possess that relative independ- NATURE OF THE 'WORLD-STUFF.' 97 ence which we designate when we say that it is 'outside' of God. § 57. Hence it would follow (what we now remark only incidentally) that, with respect to our entire view of the World, we find ourselves in the presence of an alternative. If spiritual life is the only form in which we can conceive of a reality that is not a mere state of some other real being, then our current idea of a motionless, blind and lifeless 'stuff,' which should exist outside of us, can signify nothing that is actual. We must either assume, as the Idealist does, that what we regard as such a ' stuff ' has no existence external to spirits, but that the self- coherent semblance of such a 'world-stuff' (com pare especially J. G. Fichte), is merely produced within these spirits, and for them only, by a universal power which works in all spirits. Or else we must conclude, in entire agreement with the Spiritualists, that each atom of that which appears to us as mere 'stuff,' is after all something better than this ; that is to say, it participates in the most general characteristic of the spiritual life : and this characteristic consists in somehow (either in distinct consciousness or in 98 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. the mere feeling of pleasure and pain) 'being for self,' and not in merely forming an object of con templation for others. It is only the common realistic opinion on this subject that would seem to us impossible, accord ing to which an entirely ' selfless stuff ' would be just as actually existent outside of us as we are wont commonly to represent it. There is no doubt that either of the two fore going views may be formed into an entirely con sistent apprehension of the world. But from the religious point of view, we are not necessarily required to choose between them. § 58. If however there were in existence noth ing more than an indefinite number of such inde pendent, created beings, there would still be no foundation for the conception of a government of the world. It would still be thinkable, that the world might develop itself in a perfectly impertur bable harmony ; and the problem for all spirits would consist in merely looking on, and in con sciously and admiringly rejoicing in this fact. In point of fact, however, religious sentiment has never been satisfied with this, but has always insisted, at the outset very obscurely although vig orously, that something new also must happen in POSSIBILITY OF SOMETHING NEW. 99 the world, — something that is not a mere conse quence of what has gone before ; — and that there must exist in individual spirits just this capacity to initiate a new series of events ; and therefore in brief a freedom of acting or primarily of willing, by which they separate themselves from the Uni versal Substance in a still more decided manner than by their mere 'Being for self as relatively independent beings. In this way then has the problem originated which leads to the conception of a government. For only after this is there any possibility of -events by which the continuous realization of a predeterminate plan of the world might be inter rupted. § 59. Even the above-mentioned demand for free dom would have no religious significance, if it were directed in a merely formal way to the possibility of new beginnings. For that something new hap pen in the world, has of itself no more value than that the whole course of the world be an unin terrupted, consecutive process of development ; in which of itself also, as we have already previously suggested, there is involved nothing that is worthy of adoration. But we know surely, that we only demand this TOO PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. formal ' freedom ' because we regard it as the con- ditio sine qua non for the fulfilment of ethical com mands, whose obligatory majesty we consider to be the most absolute certainty and one that needs no derivation from any other source whatever. This conviction is the absolutely fundamental point upon which the entire religious character of our view of the world depends. And for him who does not directly experience and acknowledge this, all questions of religious philosophy are altogether superfluous. § 60. The ideas of freedom are not induced by speculation ; but they rest entirely upon the fact of that penitence and self-condemnation in which we believe we find the immediate assurance of the possibility, that the choice, whose failure is now repented of, might have been reached even sooner than it was. This idea is, in an obscure way, the first and most natural, the one that has precedence in hu man culture. It was not till a later period that the scientific contemplation of nature disclosed the con ception of a ' necessary causal connection,' and then extended it over the whole course of the world, so that now the idea of freedom seems like a strange exception and as such is denied, It is POSSIBILITY OF FREE CHOICE. IOI acknowledged that even the ethical ideals origi nate in the mechanical course of psychical develop ment. But how much influence they have upon our action, depends entirely upon the involuntary states and movements within our own interior being. It is therefore due to a process of nature, that the impulse to good actions, or even to bad actions, preponderates within us ; and the mechan ical conditions for such result may be strengthened by a correct or by a perverted education. But, to be consistent and candid about it, an action in the proper sense, such as would issue from our own ego, will then no longer exist. And even the inducement to all such reflection — that is, the feel ing of penitence — will be regarded as a disagree able state, about like a feeling of sickness ; and it will be maintained that the wish involved in this feeling, — the wish that one had acted differ ently, — gives no assurance whatever of this hav ing been possible at an earlier moment. Such views as the foregoing are not to be got at by speculation ; they involve no contra diction of cognition. If they are abandoned, it can be done only upon the basis of an undemon- strable belief, that after all there is directly dis closed in the aforesaid self-condemnation, the pos sibility of a free choice, without which 'the bad 102 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. conscience' and the pain of 'penitence' would con tinue to be totally inexplicable phenomena in a rational order of the world. § 61. We cannot think of doing more than refute the objections against the possibility of the con ception of freedom ; we cannot think of proving its actual validity. Now, in the first place, it should be remembered that 'freedom' and 'causality' are not absolutely opposed to each other, but are compatible with each other; that is to say, the former would pos tulate the latter, but of course the latter would not the former. For every free beginning of an action must demand that, in the world into which it intends to introduce an event a, all Things cohere firmly and according to law ; so that from a only the intended result z can follow, and not any other at pleasure. Consequently 'freedom' is only to be accepted in the sense of an influence upon a world causally ordered. Since however the free action ought to be sub jected to an ethical judgment, it must be added that the decision with respect also to what is 'good' or 'bad,' is made in entire independence of the will. Therefore, freedom also is to be accepted only in the sense of a choice between POSSIBILITY OF UNCONDITIONED CHOICE. IO3 what has value and what has not value, — perma nently, and for its own sake. The further objection, — namely that a freedom, in the sense intended by us, that is in the disrep utable sense of a completely ' unconditioned ' choice between a and non-a, is in respect of the process of its action incomprehensible, — is likely to be mis understood : it does not raise a special obstacle such as positively to prohibit the conception of freedom, but simply and absolutely denies its valid ity. For, assuming that there is freedom, it is involved in its very conception, that the process of the decision it makes cannot be a ' comprehen sible ' one ; because this would presuppose that the decision follows as the consequence of a succes sion of reciprocally conditioning circumstances, and therefore does not follow freely. If now offence is still taken at this incomprehensibility of freedom, it may be borne in mind, that the process of causal action would be no less obscure, and the fact of something effectuating something else, as regards its succession of events, just as incomprehensible. If then it is still argued, that at all events such a capacity of choosing arbitrarily and blindly be tween a and non-a is irrational and unworthy of any respect, it is to be considered that we in fact neither commend nor venerate the 'freedom ' IO4 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. that has not yet decided. It is only the ' will ' which is no longer free, but has made its decision, that merits commendation or censure. ' Freedom ' is simply the conditio sine qua non for the possibility of the subsequent valuation of the determinate act of willing. For although we may concede that it is just the volition itself which we commend or censure, while we do not demand that this volition itself be re peated once more, still we after all tacitly pre suppose in such a case, that just this ' volition ' from the very outset has the significance of a decision sprung from 'freedom.' If this is denied us, and the will is defined as an emotion which originates mechanically within us, then we deny that ethical predicates are at all applicable to the will as a mere process of nature. On the other hand it is objected, that the Good ought to be chosen for its own sake, but not in an entirely arbitrary manner : a blind freedom there fore would be just as little conducive to actions which may be judged ethically. In reply to this it is to be observed, that we can never speak of a ' blind ' will ; since all volition belongs to the same spiritual subject, which on the other hand is en dowed likewise with the consciousness of the pos sible modes of its action and of their values. If VARYING INFLUENCE OF WILL. IO5 such a subject in possession of this consciousness makes a choice, its choice at all events is not ' blind.' But there is no necessity for apprehending the presence in consciousness of the correct esti mate of the possible modes of action as at the same time a determining influence which neces sarily conditioned the direction of the will. One difficulty however remains. The act of voli tion, although itself not causally conditioned, would still, if there is to be any corresponding result, be obliged to have a varying influence upon the existing states of the mind. And now the ques tion comes, as to the means that determined the intensity with which the ' freely ' originated will either overcomes the states of passion that strug gle against it, or else yields to them. It would be a somewhat sophistical piece of information to affirm unqualifiedly that only the volition, but not the accomplishment of it is free ; and indeed to carry this to such extent, that not only the pos sibility of the execution of an external action when willed would be doubtful, but that even the inner states of the mind also would form for the will a sort of external world, in which it could validate itself only in case the states of the same are more over in harmony with its demands. In a somewhat indefinite form this thought ap- IO6 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. pears in the sphere of religion : we pray God to grant strength to the well-disposed but weak will ; we therefore certainly ascribe volition to the hu man spirit, and only doubt about its needful power. A decisive judgment upon this question it is hardly possible to find. To assume an entirely free 'volition' and to include in the conception of it its complete ineffectiveness seems almost absurd : on the contrary the other extreme opin ion is a very bold one and hardly to be accepted ; namely, that just as the will freely determines its own direction, so also is it able to determine its own intensity, and that it is always the willing spirit's own fault, if it has too little intensity of volition to overcome the involuntary psychical im pulses to action. § 62. According to the entire foregoing discus sion, acceptance or rejection of freedom will ulti mately be a matter of decision, and not the result of a theoretical demonstration. It is only on the assumption, that we do not hold the speculative difficulties which we encounter to be insuperable, and that we therefore believe in the freedom of spiritual beings, that there is any further interest in discussing the conception of a government of the world. GOVERNMENT AND PRESERVATION. IO/ Government, in contradistinction to Preservation, could only consist in immediate influences of God upon the order of nature, such as were not included in the proper consequences of this order. And these influences could only be occasioned by the free actions which threaten to turn the prog ress of the world's course aside from a prescribed line. Such divine influences are comprehended under the name of Miracles. In order to estimate this conception, it must not be defined as an abolition of the order of nature in general, or of the general laws of na ture. For then the conception would not at all correspond to what we mean by it. ' General ' sus- spension of the 'laws of nature' would only occa sion a chaos which is utterly beyond the power of representation. The ' miracle ' however is supposed to be a definite event, in which, in a single instance and with reference to definite things and for definite moments, the physical laws are invalidated which, contemporaneously or previously and subsequently, continued to be valid with respect to all other things. This however means nothing but that the nature a of some one element experiences a change into IO8 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. o, by which it now no longer falls under the do main of the natural law g, but under that of an other -y ; and in consequence of this it no longer produces the ordinary effect, but another and ex traordinary one. According to this definition, there fore, the miracle in general would involve no alteration whatever of the laws of nature, but only the change of one or more magnitudes to which those laws are applied. Now it cannot be disputed, that such a change of the natures of single elements by the influence of a divine intervention is just as thinkable as it would be if accomplished by the intervention of another, and that a physical force. And particu larly under the presupposition, that the Things of nature are not independent, but are products con stantly supported by a divine power, does this general conception of the miracle contain, on the one hand, all that can be demanded in the re ligious interest, and, on the other, nothing that would be theoretically contradictory or impossible. § 63. There is no cause for overmuch rejoicing on account of this proof of the mere abstract conceivableness of the miracle. On the contrary it must be lamented, that we lack every decisive scientific regulative for determining the limits, MIRACLES AS RELATED TO SPIRITS. IOQ within which we may have confidence in this possibility of thought, as valid in actuality. Only very indefinite thoughts upon this question admit of being presented. That the order of nature for its own sake is in need of no corrections, is obvious. And the changes, which the free actions of spirits are able to produce in it, are so narrowly limited and may be so easily compensated for by the general economy of nature, that even for their sake ' miraculous ' interventions are incredible. Although, on the other hand, we feel a certain aesthetic inclination to behold great crises of history, in which a new phase of spiritual devel opment has its beginning, made glorious by extraordinary changes of physical conditions also ; still we must acknowledge that we can prove neither the necessity nor the real benefit which would result from satisfying our fancy by this summons of the miraculous. It seems therefore, that it is not at all nature directly, but primarily the inner life of the world of spirits only, that forms the object, to which immediate interventions in the government of the world could have relation ; and this in such manner that the interventions would not make use of the individual spirits merely as passive points of tran- IIO PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. sition, but would supply their own activity with inducements and incentives, which the external course of nature cannot offer them. Moreover, by means of these inducements and incentives they would succeed, in accordance with the ordi nary laws of the spiritual life, in introducing into the world new beginnings of spiritual movement that are in conformity with the plan of the world. If in these events we include among others re ligious visions also, then we do not conceive them to be, as Rationalism does, merely subjective delu sions to which nothing in external nature, and consequently nothing whatever corresponds. On the contrary, we think of them as products of a reciprocal action of God with individual spirits by means of which there is brought to pass in them an ideal appearance of a truly valid content ; and this content would gain nothing whatever in dig nity, value or reality, if it were realized, not merely as such appearance, but as physical or ma terial actuality besides. § 64. Accordingly it is impossible speculatively to determine, how far within the limits of proba bility, faith in the applicability of the not essen tially impossible conception of miracle ought to be extended. HISTORY NOT MERE DEVELOPMENT. 1 1 I The entire thought however, in which the in clination towards this faith has its source, is still further in harmony with the idea of a history for the world in which we come to participate with God in some common experience. And while this is something which is determined in accord ance with his most general plan, it is still in its details by no means the mere result of original predestination. It is therefore not merely ' de velopment ' according to the law of reason and consequent, but actual history ; and this history is without exception found only where general laws or a general plan are not executed with perfect constancy, but in alternate action with innumerable lawless obstacles or free counteractions. This summing-up of actuality into a history which has beginning, middle and end, is very natural to all religions. And yet there are no doubt dif ficulties involved in such an idea in itself con sidered. That is to say, it seems to us at first as if the proper determination of actuality consists in the historical actualization of a " world-aim " or in the struggle toward it. And with this understanding of the matter, it is altogether natural to regard the creation, the history of the world, and the judg ment of the world, as three successive acts of such 112 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. a concluded drama. But upon closer consideration after all this view is in contradiction to our needs. If the world was created in time, so that reckon ing from this (present) moment a retrogressive cognition should, after a finite number of steps, discover its beginning, then we are troubled by the emptiness of infinite time before this beginning ; and we know of nothing with which to fill it out. For even the thought of a solitary preexistence of God is an obscure one, supposing that the creation of the world is made to originate from an act of the will of God, which could have no need of this preparatory period either for its origination or for its execution. Just so if the judgment of the world is the conclusion of history, it certainly cannot be under stood to mean that the created actuality would now vanish again into nothingness. Rather is it only by this judgment of the world that there is established an order of things which fulfils the* aim of the world, and which would then naturally be perpetuated ad infinitum as the actuality of that which ought to be ; — and this without ex periencing any further history of that development, which would now be superfluous. Such considerations convince us that the idea THE PERIODS OF THE WORLD. 1 13 of these three successive periods of Beginning, Realization and Completion of an aim, — derived as it is from our human endeavors, — is not ap plicable to the totality of the world. CHAPTER VIII. OF THE CONCEPTION OF THE 'WORLD-AIM.' § 65. The conception of a 'world-aim,' which, according to the remarks we have just made, would not be realized all at once at the conclusion of a history, but progressively in the course of the world, we have simply introduced without any question as to its validity. Speculatively it is by no means to be demonstrated ; it continues to be perfectly possible to think of the course of the world as an entirely purposeless, although more or less living development of an Absolute. But religious feeling has an immediate evidence that the case is not so, and that all the phenomena of inspiration, of adoration, and of the feeling of obligation to an ideal, are not explicable as casual effects in the development of a purposeless Prin ciple. But if the conception of a supreme aim for the world is once acknowledged, then the other ideas, which form its necessary points of relation, comport with it ; and especially the idea of a per sonal God, in whose consciousness and will alone this aim, previous to its full accomplishment, can PLACE OF THE SUPREME AIM. 115 have any actuality by means of which it becomes effective as guiding principle for the course of the world itself. To this subject however we are not going to return. The most urgent question is, wherein are we to place this ' supreme aim.' § 66. The answer to the foregoing question is to this extent self-evident, that naturally this aim cannot be placed in the realization of a fact, with respect to which the further question were possi ble ; why just this, and not other conceivable aims of like nature, is to fill this supremely exalted position in the world. The aim must obviously be that which has supreme value, and with respect to which the aforesaid question becomes senseless. Now as to what this aim is, the common, unphil- osophical religious view is not at all uncertain : nothing but the conception of blessedness seems to it to express this value, with respect to which it is absurd to raise the question, why this and why nothing else constitutes the supreme aim. It may be incidentally remarked, that the exist ence of a world of spirits is connected with the foregoing view as something conceivable. For only such a world could contain the subjects whose states this supreme aim may be conceived to be. On the Il6 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. other hand, this view by no means also furnishes at once an explanation of the existence of this determinate, /^animate world. § 67. The above-mentioned view is combated in vain from the side of an ethical Rigorism, which, through its well-known undervaluation of all 'pleas ure,' always in the practical domain, regards noth ing but disinterested obedience to the universal commands of duty as ethical ; and therefore in the religious domain also would not in any case be disposed to acknowledge ' supreme blessedness ' as the final purpose of the world, — perhaps not, with any readiness, even as a tolerable conse quence of that purpose. With respect to this point we briefly remark as follows : If obedience or disobedience to an ethical law were to occasion not a trace of pleas ure or pain to any sensitive being in the world, — whether God, angels, or men, — it would be utterly incomprehensible, why it is just the obedi ence and not the disobedience to the law that must have an obligatory force ; since after all the effects of the two modes of conduct consist only in the production of different states of fact, one of which would be as indifferent as the other. In a word, it is impossible to understand what THE NATURE OF THE GOOD. I \"J is to constitute the ' value ' of any action, if its results are not able to produce some 'Good' some where in the world, or to increase the sum of already existing 'Good.' But while we designate Things, States and Events as ' Good,' it is after all only in so far as they are means for obtain ing the only real and substantial ' Good ' ; and this latter always exists only in the pleasure of some sensitive spirit, and would vanish with the world of spirits completely from the realm of ac tuality. No Ethics can avoid having regard to a pur pose that is final and in itself of absolute value. No matter to what extent many rigorous systems formulate their highest ethical laws apparently without any such regard, still, in addition to the assurances that they are the highest laws, the conclusion must always be supplied : What then would be the result, if these laws were not obeyed ? § 68. The foregoing assertions do not degrade morals. It is not meant by them, that the direct endeavor after happiness — and that, too, after one's own happiness — should be the ethically praise worthy motive of our action. On this point our conscience gives us sufficient instruction ; since it interprets this endeavor as in itself considered Il8 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. indifferent and merely natural, but on the con trary interprets as ethically laudable only the endeavor to secure the happiness of others. Thus (as might be further proved) the command of ' benevolence ' is, among all ethical commands, really the fundamental one ; and only upon the assumption of it do all the rest receive their ob ligatory value. On the other hand, in seeking a coherent view of the world, we have a speculative interest in the fact that the ethical commands, which we are able in practice to obey without any further question as to their origin, are not wholly lacking in co herence with the arrangement of the world. That such arrangement therefore be reckoned to the account of the final purpose of blessedness, is a speculative claim, which we set up in the in terest, to a certain extent, of our reverence for the world, but not for the satisfaction of our own wishes for happiness. We are naturally unable to avoid including our own welfare also in this com prehensive final purpose. The foregoing are perhaps the incentives which in religious thought have led to this doctrine of blessedness. From these incentives are distin guished, and not to their advantage, at least as regards the intention, the philosophical systems BLESSEDNESS AS AN ABSTRACT NOTION. 1 19 which only in a practical way set up claims upon our obedience to universal ethical laws, but specu- latively give us no enlightenment with respect to the ultimate end, to which properly this ceaseless expenditure of ethical energy is to lead. § 69. Certainly, the laudation alluded to above holds good only of the intention and not of the performance of this religious opinion. It is wrecked rather in the attempt, actually to deduce the neces sity of the present world from the supreme purpose of blessedness. The first objection certainly might be disre garded ; namely, why this purpose could be accom plished at all only as a result of a course of the world, and why it could not be accomplished as well from the very beginning. At the foundation of such a question there really lies the logical error of regarding the conception of ' blessedness ' or of ' pleasure in general ' in this universal sense of it, as something realizable. But the 'pleasure' that is without content can no more exist than a sen sation of ' color in general,' which were neither green nor blue. Every ' pleasure ' is rather an altogether determinate one, which is distinguished, as to its intensity and coloring, from others, and in both respects is determined by the nature of the content of which it is an enjoyment. I2O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. Hence it may be made evident, that we are utterly unable to form any real idea of a blessed ness without content, although we can form the name of it ; that it is capable of realization rather only upon the supposition that there are actual relations of some sort, which constitute the object of enjoyment in this pleasure ; and, finally, that even these relations cannot be as they will, but together must form an orderly arrangement of the world. But no progress is made in the foregoing way ; the postulates which are set up with respect to such an arrangement of the world, are always after all general and abstract. That they had to be realized now by means of just these substances, forces, organisms, and kinds of occurrence, which we discover empirically in the world, is in nowise to be proved. Wonder at the fact that so many other kinds of existence were still possible, which however do not exist, can be modified but imperfectly by the intimation that our range of experience is narrow, and that perhaps there are realized in the extra- earthly world all the possibilities which we miss upon the surface of the earth. For since we have reason to think that the most general physical laws, which are valid with us, are valid also for all distant THE EXISTENCE OF EVIL. 121 parts of the world, therefore the organizations also which are there found can only be such as are in accordance with these laws. There always remains as conceivable, however, an infinite manifoldness that might exist, if those laws were only different. We are therefore brought round to the new question : Why are the laws of nature, which are not necessities of thought but empirical, precisely as they are and not otherwise ? This question is unanswerable ; and in our religious faith we must be content to think of the given world as in fact called to the realization of the supreme pur pose, without being able to investigate any further the grounds of this calling. § 70. The existence of evil in the world — and that too primarily of mere physical evil — brings our general assumptions still further into inex plicable contradiction with our data of facts. It is sufficient to indicate in a word, how utterly fruitless are those ways of speaking which seek to apologize for evil by recognizing it only " in particulars," but maintaining " the harmony of the world as a whole." One needs only to reverse these utterances : " On the whole the world makes a beautiful figure indeed, but in particulars it is wretched," — in order to understand that such ex- 122 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. pressions give evidence merely of the good inten tion of the apology, but specify no ground for such an apology. . Moreover the assertion of that " harmony on the whole " is in fact by no means whatever to be demonstrated. We merely know that the world does not perish on account of its imperfections, but that both it and they continue together. § 71. All efforts to attain to clearness upon the above-mentioned subject, can only try to apologize for the evil that does not admit of being done away with by denial. The first onset for this purpose consists in the assumption that evil is necessary ; in other words that God, although having in view only the High est Good, has nevertheless been bound in his creation to laws which have not permitted the un conditioned Good, but only the choice of the best world among many, all of which were imperfect. The limitation of the divine Omnipotence which is involved in this view, might be tolerated to a certain extent, if the aforesaid general laws were really understood to be simply the eternal truths, which, as we saw, are nothing extraneous to God, but are only the proper modus agendi of his own spiritual activity. But there is nothing whatever THE ORIGIN OF EVIL. in the whole world by which to prove that these eternal truths were to blame for the evils that are in the world. So far as we are in any way empirically acquainted with the course of things, and are able, according to its analogy, to judge of non-realized possibilities, an absolutely faultless world would not be at all inconsistent with those 'eternal truths.' The ground of evil, so far as we know, lies rather in those special facts and arrangements, which are in actual existence, but instead of which there might as well be others that were also on friendly terms with the afore said truths and yet would not lead to these evils. Since now we must attribute the establishment of these special actualities to the creative will of God, the attempt in this way to make the origin of evil independent of the divine will would not succeed ; for his omnipotence would have still further to be so limited that even the actual ele ments of the world and their original combina tions would be regarded as something taken for granted, in the midst of which God would have to find himself existing, and from which He then would have to endeavor to secure the best result still possible (Leibnitz). This would be not only a degradation of our conception of God from a religious point of view, 124 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. but it would also be speculatively fruitless. For in order that the measurable influence upon the world, which is still attributed to such a God, might be able to exist at all, a second superior God would have to be assumed, who, in the manner previously discussed (§§ 16 ff.), would com prehend both of these now mutually indifferent members in one reciprocal action, and would pre vail upon them to act upon each other. § 72. After the foregoing explanation which is intended as metaphysical, there is one of a peda gogic sort, that regards evil as a means of Good, that is of education and improvement. But in the first place this view merely contem plates men, who alone are capable of education. But in the animal world as well physical evils appear ; and that not at all in a sporadic manner, but so systematized that the terrible torture and destruction of one class of creatures by the rest belongs directly to the so-called order of Nature. No pedagogic can make this comprehensible. We can much sooner comprehend how earlier times in despair over this very fact set a ' bad Principle ' in a dualistic manner over against the Good. But even leaving this out of the account, — any education makes use of evil simply because MORAL AND PHYSICAL EVIL. the minds which it intends to affect, are psycho logically so defectively organized, that without this intrinsically objectionable means the end would no longer be realized. If it were applied to the entire world, it would lead back to the previous thought : God did not have it in his power to make the world so perfect that it would attain its end without corrections by means of evil. § 73. A view which has been elaborated rather in a religious and mystical way, regards the mor ally Bad as prior and physical evil as a consequence of its becoming actual. Now the circumstance that the truly Good was not to be actualized without the possibility of the Bad, and therefore that the freedom of the world of spirits was to be conceded, we can consider as a necessity which need not be foreign even to God's own nature. But after all we do not understand, why the bad 'disposition which entered the world in consequence of such freedom needed to have any physical result at all ; and why the danger which it threatened to the undisturbed continuance of the world, was not averted by one of those self-compensations, by means of which so frequently elsewhere in nature the be- 126 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. ginning of a disturbed equipoise cancels itself again. The necessary existence of freedom would there fore by no means show that the innocent must suffer by its misuse. But in addition to this also the view does not cover the whole question. For the further assumption that nature was originally without evil and that sin first brought it into the world, not only lacks all empirical foundation, but is even in itself considered un tenable. We cannot, just because individual spirits, or even very many of them, erred, regard ' sin ' as a unit-principle or a power which would have a legitimate influence upon the course of nature in general ; still less is it - to be understood, why na ture did not endeavor to overcome singly the dis turbances which the sin that is foreign to it had introduced, instead of admitting physical evils, as a kind of solidaric totality, into the very plan of its operations. The incomprehensibleness of the foregoing views is not lessened by their being proclaimed with still greater emphasis ; thus, for example, by speaking of a " voluntary fall of the entire creation " which now extends "the curse of its imperfection to all creatures that still spring from it." In whatever way the picture may be painted, to attribute this EVIL AN 1NSOLVABLE ENIGMA. \2"J act of a 'fall' to the collective conception of a creation means after all nothing whatever. It is intelligible only as regards each particular, indi vidual, free and conscious being. But if we refer it to such a being, then it is a perfect monstrosity, at variance with the simplest sense of justice, to assume that the consequences of this act pass over, as an inheritance which it is impossible to shake off, to all later generations, although they are according to their very conception destined to like 'freedom.' In very different forms have Mythology, Mysti cism and Dogmatics represented such a primaeval history of the world. But none of these attempts has been able to eliminate the aforesaid manifest incongruities. § 74. The above-mentioned incapacity of our spec ulative cognition for the solution of this enigma of evil had to be very plainly expressed. For there ought not to remain any seeming as if there were, in expressions which cannot be understood and which only commend themselves to the imagination through intuitive images, any real speculative proof for the correctness of the religious feeling upon which rests our faith in a good and holy God, and in the destination of the world to the attainment of a blessed end. 128 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. He who does not share this religious conviction, may, on account of these last considerations of ours, very easily from a speculative point of view reach that Pessimism, which is just now the order of the day, and for which there will be on specu lative grounds no refutation. But this Pessimism, which reverts to the thought of an original energy without will, that produces the Good and the Bad alike without design, is not a profound view but is just that cheap and superficial kind of view, by which all enigmas are conveniently disposed of — by simply sacrificing all that is most essential and supreme to the unprejudiced mind. In contrast with this Pessimism, the more diffi cult problem is the firm confidence that, in spite of all that is incomprehensible to us, the striving after a supreme end is at all events extant in the world. For this confidence takes upon itself the great and ever unavoidable task of always making renewed attempts to fill the gap which lies be tween this content of our faith and our actual experiences. If we call every attempt of this sort in thought or action ' Religion,' then ' religion ' is never ex actly a demonstrable theorem, but the conviction of its truth is a deed that is to be accredited to character. CHAPTER IX. RELIGION AND MORALITY. § 75. If there is no speculative argument for religious conviction, still there must be a motive for holding fast this conviction. And in fact an appeal has constantly been made to an 'immediate inner experience,' which attests the truth of the content of religion, as directly and independently of the intervention of logic as perception by the senses attests the reality of external objects. It has already been said in the Introduction however, that there by no means exists an harmonious inner experience as regards that divine order of the world which is not perceivable by the senses ; but rather that (compare also § 59) the only ele ment common to men, to which an appeal may be made for the confirmation of religion, consists in those ' utterances of the conscience ' that pri marily only say what ought to be, and yet after all permit an indirect inference from this as to what is. § 76. There are different ways of apprehend ing this real function of the ' conscience ' also. I3O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. It must be acknowledged that the conscience is not, prior to all experience, a coherent revela tion of the commands to which our future conduct ought to conform ; the rather is it like our capa city of cognition. The supreme principles to which this capacity reduces its judgment of Things, are also no original ready-made posses sion of our consciousness. Particular perceptions rather induce us, in the first place, as a sort of immediate reaction, to effect their combination so as to give them a definite significance. It is only subsequent reflection upon many such par ticular cases, that shows us in accordance with what ' principles ' our conduct, which was pre viously only instinctive, has proceeded. And now for the first time are they conscious prin ciples, to which we conform in our subsequent cognition. Just so 'conscience' is first induced, by consid ering cases that are quite definite, to pass par ticular judgments of approval or disapproval upon actions which are brought before it. It is only by reflective comparison of these particular judg ments, that there is formed from them those general ethical precepts, which it is then cus tomary to designate as the 'immediate voice of conscience.' THE VIEW OF EGOISM. 131 § 77. This necessary concession with respect to the psychological development of our conscience, is now made use of to support in the first place a view, which annuls the obligatory value and the proper majesty of ethical commands. It is the view, namely, that the sensibility which induces the spirit to approve or disapprove of some definite act itself rests in turn merely upon the immediate well-being or ill-being, which the spirit experiences from it. When however this sensibility proceeds to the formation of gen eral propositions, it comprises only those maxims, constant obedience to which experience has taught secures on the average the highest degree and steadiest permanence of that well-being which is at all attainable. All ethical commands accord ingly appear merely as maxims of that Egoism which seeks its own self-preservation ; they appear however as general laws simply for the reason that the limitation of our cognition of the past, present and future, does not in every case permit that mode of action which is specially suited to these different periods, for the attainment of the highest possible good. To this entire mode of apprehending the sub ject we must now concede this one point, — namely, that the mere experience of human inter- 132 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. course certainly may furnish us with the concrete and determinate particular content of those pre cepts, in conforming to which ethical behavior consists ; and that, on the other hand, all at tempts in a reverse direction to deduce those specialized precepts from the general conceptions of the Good, the Ethical, the Holy, or the Just, are in vain. Such general conceptions express nothing whatever but the peculiar character of the impression, which definite kinds of conduct will make upon our feelings, as soon as we shall become acquainted with them : on the other hand, they do not acquaint us with just those forms of the conduct itself, to which this impression will apply. § 78. A disposition which insists upon endeavor ing to find in ethical precepts nothing but pru dential maxims acquired by experience, and to find back of all actions nothing but egoistic motives, can in no way be gainsaid by mere speculation. So much only is clear, namely, that such an interpre tation of moral commands is arbitrary. For in that case also, supposing us to assume that a worth and sacredness of their own belongs to these com mands, everything would still be exactly the same. That is to say, these commands would in fact be THE VIEW OF EGOISM. 133 the maxims, conforming to which produces the greatest amount of happiness. The content more over of that which they command would always be learned first by experience, as was previously mentioned. And for just this reason it would always be possible to represent them as though they were nothing more than such lessons of experience with respect to what is expedient. But on the other hand, he who prefers this interpretation overlooks the fact, that we all of us none the less set over against the conduct which simply conforms to these maxims of prudence, another of an altogether different sort, as being the only one of value ; and this latter conduct con forms to these same maxims, although with differ ent sentiments ; and indeed with such sentiments as either have disinterested regard to the estab lishment of the Good, in precisely the same way, for instance, in which we reverence beauty as having objective value without advantage to ourselves — or else with such sentiments as find happiness, so far as they make the production of it an object of pursuit, only in benevolence towards others and not in selfishness. This also may be denied ; but in denying it there is involved the denial of an inner experience, upon the acknowledgment of which every further 134 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. upward flight of religion depends. Conversely, therefore, it will not be possible to gainsay those who are conscious of this inner experience. § 79. But even the recognition of the peculiar worth and sacredness of ethical commands does not lead at once to a religious view of the world ; on the contrary this recognition, in ancient as well as mod ern times, has been put in express opposition to religious thoughts, which seemed like a needless and false supplement to it. It is not to be denied, that practically even this Stoicism, or the Rational ism which disdains any connection with religion, may, by mere subordination to the general demands of morality and of the course of the world, furnish the basis for a conduct of life well deserving of rec ognition. But there are involved in this conception (compare § 68) peculiar speculative contradictions. It is maintained in the first place, that all thoughts about an origin at some time or other, or about an ultimate aim of moral laws, are to be avoided, because they could only serve to corrupt the conception of the peculiar sacredness and un conditioned obligation of these laws, which demand rather an altogether immediate recognition as being absolutely obligatory. Worthy of respect as is the sentiment which is thus expressed, yet the specu- AN 'UNCONDITIONED OUGHT.' 135 lative thought, by which it would like to sustain itself, is utterly unserviceable. Laws that are com pletely unconditioned may be conceived of, so far forth as they in fact govern all actuality, like the laws of nature, and are consequently expressions of a 'must' which knows no exceptions. On the con trary the thought of an ' unconditioned Ought/ that is, of a law to which actuality in no wise of itself corresponds, is incomprehensible. There must be a difference between the reality of that which oiight to be and of that which ought not to be ; and this difference cannot consist in the mere repetition of these two antithetical predi cates. Rather must the very consideration, that the one ought to be and the other ought not to be, have a practical validity. In other words and more simply : An unconditioned ' Ought ' is unthinkable ; and only a conditioned Ought is possible, which attaches advantages and disadvantages to the ob servance or non-observance of what is prescribed. These very consequences, however, may still con sist ultimately only in pleasure or pain. And in this alone also consists the ' absolute value,' as it is called, which the ideals of conduct designated by moral laws possess. A value, which is valued by no one, and therefore causes no one pleasure or pain, is, according to our previous explanation (§ 67), an essentially self-contradictory thought. 136 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. Now the advantage, which must be inseparably connected with the claim to validity for the moral laws, could be sought primarily in that immobility of feeling, that ataraxy, which Stoicism regards as the ideal of life for the wise man. But if this is commendable so far as it does not permit disturb ance by the passions, still there is little that is commendable in its consequence, which would also exclude living enthusiasm for the Good and Beauti ful, and would virtually degrade the feeling spirit to the form in which an impersonal substance ex ists. The moral laws, however, so far as this ataraxy would be attained by observing them, would in fact still be mere maxims of utility, which would be designed for the attainment of a completely ego istic well-being. It is manifestly, however, not this tranquillity of mind alone that has been in view as the ulti mate goal and good, but the self-esteem which is secured by observance of the moral laws. Now this may without doubt be very well meant, but to say the least it is not compatible with the refusal of all further religious views. If we regard the individual personality as only a product of nature, which transiently appears and then van ishes, it is not possible to understand just why we attach any value to the fact that what we PRINCIPLES OF ALL RELIGION, 137 * revere as good and holy must have its realization in just such an ' Ego ' as this. Self-esteem also would therefore be immediately intelligible as an ultimate goal only in case it were brought under the conception of that which ministers to our egoistic well-being, in the same way as does every sensuous satisfaction. It would be possi ble for it to have a different significance only in case our view of our own personality, and of its position in the totality of the world be changed. § 80. The foregoing reflections, which con fessedly have not the value of demonstrations in the proper sense, but are merely intended to make us sensible of the connection by which the particular thoughts here mentioned, first get their complete satisfaction, lead us now to three propositions which we may regard as the character istic convictions of every religious apprehension, in contradistinction to a merely intellectual view of the world, — namely : (1) Ethical laws we designate as the will of God ; (2) Individual finite spirits we designate not as products of nature, but as children of God ; (3) Actuality we designate not as a mere course of the world, but as a kingdom of God. These three propositions are to be elucidated and their consequences investigated. 138 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. § 81. The first of the above-mentioned propo sitions has raised objections, which ultimately lead to the well-known scholastic alternative : ' Is the Good good, because God wills it ? or does He will it, because it is good ? ' This point is to be decided according to the analogy of the similar question as to the validity of eternal truths. If one would answer the first member of the alternative in the affirmative, the question would be asked : What then is comprehended under the thought of that God, who appears here as the sub ject of this will ? He would be nothing but an infinite Power, as yet wholly devoid of content ; and the affirmation, that He has willed the Good (if it meant a determination of will issued in time, quite as much as if it declared this will, to be one without beginning and eternal) would really be precisely identical with the other assertion, — namely, the Good is assumed to be once for all in existence, and a ' positing ' or ' affirming,' wholly without origin, is the basis of this assumption. It is moreover obvious, that every such deed of mere power, while it may impart necessity, cannot impart worth to the command. But then, on the other hand, it is just as fruitless to assert that God wills the Good because it is GOD THE INTRINSICALLY GOOD. 139 'intrinsically good.' For, to say nothing about the ambiguity of this latter expression, an ac knowledgment of the Good, which is not a merely enforced decree in subordination to a statute, would after all be possible only in case the con tent to be acknowledged already possesses for the nature of the acknowledging spirit the truth and the value which is to be awarded to it. We are convinced therefore, that the above- mentioned alternative separates again two thoughts, which must be thought together in absolute insep- arableness as the expression of a single fact ; and that we always run against absurdities, whenever we make one of these alternatives the condition for the other. We therefore come to the following decision : God is nothing else than that Will, whose con tent and modes of procedure are comprehended m our reflection as the ' intrinsically Good ' ; and which may by abstraction be separated from that living form of existence which it nowhere else possesses but precisely in the real God. In truth, however, such will of God no more follows from his nature as secondary to it, or precedes it as primary to it, than in motion — say direction can be antecedent or subsequent to velocity. It is therefore an entire mistake to object that I4O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. the peculiar majesty of moral laws suffers detri ment if they are regarded as the will of God. For we take this view of the matter, not precisely with the design of laying, by the specification of their origin, a basis for that worth of those com mands which we directly recognize ; but we do it in order to add to this worth — which, although it stands on its own foundation, we were neverthe less obliged to regard speculatively as an incom plete thought, — this supplement, by which, as we remarked, its worth is not enhanced but becomes intelligible and compatible with the totality of our view of the world. § 82. As regards the second proposition (§ 80), the somewhat sentimental way in which it is ex pressed need not deceive us with respect to the weightiness of the thought. It has a twofold mean ing. That is to say, on the one hand there is involved in it the recognition of the finiteness of the personal spirit and of its subjection to the power and wisdom of God. And herein is found the reason for that opposition which the Christian Religion especially has expressed against the pride of speculative systems of morality, that seek to attain as their ideal the self-satisfaction, self-esteem, and self-righteousness of the 'wise man.' RELATION OF MAN TO GOD. 141 The other part of this twofold meaning is the no less lively opposition to that depreciation of per sonality, which sees in it merely a transient prod uct of the course of nature. The assertion is therefore expressed in this connection, that there exists between man and God a relation of piety ; that this relation is always a vital one ; and that by means of it — but also only by means of it — the finite spirit ceases to be such absolutely de pendent product of the course of nature. The hope of being loved by God, however, takes the place of mere self-satisfaction as the Highest Good. Such approval by the Supreme Spirit sup plants the proud claim of having one's satisfaction in one's own self-esteem. § 83. With relation to the third proposition (§ 80), we have already been obliged to confess that we do not know the content and plan of the divine government of the world : and the consequence of this with respect to religion is, that the entire con sideration of external reality is withdrawn from its domain, and is regarded as an object for science, which has to ascertain its consistence by methods entirely free from prejudice, and therefore not at all influenced even by religious considerations. This attitude, too, is distinctive of Christianity. 142 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. The religions of heathenism possess a mythology, which seeks to explain and interpret, in a very cir cumstantial manner, the facts of reality. Chris tianity has no mythology and rests all its reflec tions entirely upon considerations of the spiritual world, of which we have an inner experience. CHAPTER X. DOGMAS AND CONFESSIONS. § 84. Nothing more than the content of the three propositions already cited is in fact revealed, even by the Christian Revelation. To be penetrated by their influence, and to be voluntarily subject to the divine will, as they require, constitutes a living, consolatory religious state, — or religion as a condi tion of mind. It is, nevertheless, quite impossible to avert attempts to transform this religious content, which was originally apprehended only in living presenti ment, into a series of formulated and communicable propositions. To such attempts we are impelled on the one side by our own life-experience, which desires to answer the doubts that have arisen, not always by a mere appeal to the same frame of mind, but also by convictions that enter upon the special content of the doubts raised. Under the name of religious Mysticism may be summed up the whole of these attempts at theory which are based exclusively upon one's own inner religious experience, and which also primarily claim no other validity than that 144 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. which exists for the personal subject who finds out of the depth of his own mind the desired answers to those doubts. § 85. Over against this first impulse stands a second. It is essentially self-contradictory for one to stand alone with his religious conviction, since it is just this condition which unites man to the entire universe. Religion is not merely union of the individual with God, but in and by this union it is at the same time union with all other men. In this impulse lies the one respectable root of religious Fanaticism. What we acknowledge as the Supreme, would not be such Supreme, unless it were acknowledged by all. Hence now there fol lows, not the warrant to be sure to force one's subjective views upon others, but rather that need of a religious community — now so frequently mis taken — within which each one finds again, not indeed the complete content of his own individual mysticism, but at least the outlines of the convic tion to which he is able to subordinate or to attach his own. Such therefore is the necessity of generally ac cepted Dogmas and Symbols. TWOFOLD DESIGN OF DOGMA. 145 § 86. Without doubt the historic development of such thoughts will embrace the content of religion more completely than the life-experience of an individual ; although this latter pervades with greater intensity that which has once become ob ject of such personal experience. Generally accepted objective dogmas will there fore have the twofold design, — on the one hand, to hold fast those solutions of doubt which have been gained in the course of time ; but, on the other hand, to designate certain outlines of thought beyond which our subjective fancies are not to go without exposing themselves to error. According to our previous considerations, no one of these dogmas would be, properly speaking, a speculatively or scientifically conclusive answer to a proposed question ; they would all be mere sym bols rather, which acknowledge the existence of an enigma and which by means of an insufficient figurative designation only fix the limits of that range of thoughts, beyond which the fulfilment of such postulates must not be sought. It would therefore be reckoned a mistake for us to demand of the one who purposes to belong to a religious community, an obligation binding him to the literal purport of such dogmas. It is just ac cording to their literal purport that they cannot be 146 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. objects of a confession or non-confession at all. In order that this question of confession may be raised, the dogmas need at all times an interpretation of their real meaning, — a meaning which they always indicate but imperfectly, by figures or symbols. Such interpretation however is not given objec-. tively, but each individual is in fact to find it by the activity of his own mind. It appears therefore that the only question to be put to the one who proposes to belong to a religious community is, whether he in his own heart experiences and confesses a religious truth, which admits of being comprehended as the im port of this objectively formulated dogma, and which it is worth while to have acknowledged in this particular form as a bond of union for the religious conviction of a collective body. § 87. It may be objected, that there is involved in this a sort of dissimulation. But above all things we do not maintain that religion and its dogmas are obligatory 'only for the uncultivated.' The truth of religion rather is absolutely valid for all alike ; on the contrary, the speculative expres sions which have been discovered for it, are alto gether inadequate. And for just this reason it is permitted to agree upon a formula, to which each INEXPRESSIBLE BUT TRUE RELATIONS. 147 one gives that theoretical construction by which he believes its essential meaning is best compre- • hended. In other departments of life also we are not able to discard methods of apprehending the world, which within the sphere of philosophy we nevertheless recognize as inadequate. The exist ence of a space-world outside of us, the atoms, and the forces of matter, — all these are ideas, without the use of which not only the common understand ing, but even philosophy, which denies their cor rectness, would not be at all able to find its way in its observation and treatment of the external world. In all these cases it is not so much that we get at the truth, as that we get at such an intuitive 'seeming' as is able to make intelli gible to us the essentially inexpressible, but true relations of the Actual. Just so in the case of religion it is not re quired that there be found a speculatively unob jectionable expression for that which is essentially Transcendent, but that we have figurative expres sions to which the mind may attach the same feelings that are appropriate to the proper con tent of religion. Now it is of course to be conceded that we could speak as simply as we do, only in case 148 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. these formulated dogmas were first to be estab lished. They are however already in existence, and historically considered they are surely not in all cases so perfected, that they admit of no mis understanding as to their true sense. But still this affords no reason for a wilful separation from those circles which acknowledge the dogmas ; it only involves a summons not to make of them subjects for theoretic instruction, as well as a problem of pastoral wisdom in combating the evils of a false interpretation. § 88. The attempts at theory may be reduced to three divisions, the first of which only, Theology in the narrower sense, is sufficiently accessible to phi losophy. We have endeavored in the preceding discussion to show, what more precise determinations of the Divine Being philosophy admits, what it excludes, and finally what it demands, without being able to present them in the form of adequate conceptions. As the total result of our discussion we repeat, that faith in a personal God contradicts none of those metaphysical convictions which we are com pelled to maintain ; that, on the contrary, those assertions are entirely without foundation which, with decided incredulity as regards all that is re- THEOLOGY AND THE RELIGIOUS LIFE. 149 ligious and with frivolous credulousness as regards the theories fashionable in physical science, conceive of an origin for spiritual life from the forces of mere matter ; and, finally, that the charge of an thropomorphism is entirely unjust, for the distinc tions between the infinite and the finite spirit are by no means overlooked. But it is certainly foolish to prefer to assign the Supreme Principle of the world to an unconscious blind substratum, the con ception of which is for us, strictly speaking, some thing completely dark and inscrutable. § 89. Further speculations — as for example con cerning the Trinity — would be, as regards the religious life, matters of complete indifference, but for the fact that they have been brought into con nection with the position toward God, which the human race has come to occupy by means of the establishment or revelation of religion. The con sideration in general of this position forms a sec ond grand object of religious theories. According to the conviction maintained in this discussion as to the constant activity of God in the world and upon individual spirits ; and considering our acknowledged ignorance of the precise plan which the divine government follows ; there is noth ing whatever that stands in opposition to the further I5O PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. conviction that God, at particular moments and in particular persons, may have stood nearer to humanity, or may have revealed himself at such moments and in such persons in a more eminent way than at other moments and in other persons. If therefore reverence for the founder of our religion designates him as ' Son of God,' no se rious objection to the essential thought which is expressed by this term is, in view of the preced ing paragraph, tenable ; it is even without doubt legitimate to regard the relation in which he stood to God, as absolutely unique not only as to degree but also as to its essential quality. But no one can discover an adeqtiate expression for that which would exactly correspond to the con notation of such a term (diesen Intentionen). Since then Christ after all cannot be ' God's Son ' in the literal sense, but the true meaning of this figura tive expression admits of no authentic interpreta tion whatever, this entire proposition is not at all adapted for the formation of a speculative dogma ; and he who assents to it in fact expresses merely his conviction of the unique value which Christ has for him, and which Christ's relation to God has for humanity, without however being able precisely to define either of them. SATISFACTION AND REDEMPTION. 151 § 90. He who in an unprejudiced way allows the teaching of Christ and the history of Christ's life to influence his mind, without analyzing this impression, may be convinced that an infinitely valuable and unique act has occurred here on earth for the salvation of humanity. But the attempts to settle speculatively the content and value of this fact, do not as a whole lead to the end designed. It is impossible to speak of God's honor as re ceiving ' satisfaction ' through the sacrificial death of a single person, for the injury done it by the sin of man. For such a view, aside from its some what crude conception of God, is based upon the altogether impossible conception of a solidaric unity of the human race and of the possibility of a transfer of its guilt and obligation to a single representative. The more humane ideas of a ' Reconciliation ' or a ' Redemption ' — at least the latter of them — leave it undetermined from whom it is, precisely, that humanity beholds itself delivered by this ransom. It could not well be God, but must rather be the order of natural law, which has connected sin with our finiteness and condemna tion with our sin. Now we know that we are redeemed neither 152 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. from physical evils nor from the possibility of sin. The only thing left therefore as the practically effective result of redemption is the content of a faith revealed and proffered to us, which redeems us from the distress and wretchedness of Creation, in so far as it teaches us to regard all evil as only a divine trial ; teaches us, however, to regard the whole of the earthly life, not to be sure as insig nificant, nor yet as an irrevocable finality, but as a state of preparation, for the errors of which there is in the divine grace a redemption which we are not in the least able speculatively to define. All further speculations which attach themselves to this subject — as, for example, about the origin of sin and about its consequences — are perfectly useless as regards the religious life. § 91. Even the third division of such specula tions, which we may sum up as Eschatology, does not admit of being cultivated speculatively. The earthly future of the human race as well as the nature of our immortality and of the retri bution which the final judgment will bring, are entirely beyond the reach of any concrete por trayal. And in this connection the Humanism of modern times has in fact become entirely dis used to such concrete representations, and has be- NECESSITY FOR A RELIGIOUS COMMUNITY. 153 come satisfied, as it must be, with maintaining the general faith in continued existence and in a constant process of perfection, as well as in a retribution ; and in just this way it has shown that for a truly religious life there is really no necessity whatever for that vast sum of knowl edges which dogmatics, with much liability to misunderstanding, assumes as necessary to such a life. § 92. Mention was previously made of the value attaching to the necessity that one shall not stand alone in his religious convictions. The value of this is the more enhanced on account of the fact that the content of these very convictions them-, selves consists in faith in an uninterrupted union of men with each other and with God, into which it is possible for every one to enter by his own free choice. If we call this communion the invisible Church, then the visible Church, on the other hand, is certainly nothing more than a human institution of the company of believers : partly for fellowship in the worship of God, partly for the regulation of its earthly affairs in agreement with the de mands of its faith. But every pretension which 154 PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION. such visible Church might advance, not merely to teach the way to eternal salvation and to guide to it, but to open and to shut this way by virtue of its own power, is quite unfounded. As for the rest, the Church, like every other institution, must not fall into a condition of opposition to the regu lations of the State ; although we cannot regard it as a happy expression to say that the Church must be subjected to these regulations in anything else but external matters of an altogether indiffer ent character. On the contrary, it is the evil of the present time — and of course has its historic conditions — that the State as such is compelled to exist without any religious foundation and that it believes it has no need of any. But the complete unity of the State in religious matters also, would of course presuppose that two hostile parties should return to modesty ; — namely, that theological learning on the one side, and irre ligious natural science on the other, should not assert that they have exact knowledge about so very much which they neither do know nor can know; it would therefore presuppose that, in the recognition of divine mysteries which are left to the interpretation of each individual believing mind, and of general ethical precepts concerning the THE END OF CONTROVERSY. 155 meaning of which moreover there exists no con troversy, the religious life may unfold itself in accordance with the motto : In necessariis unitas, in dubiis libertas, in omnibus caritas. INDEX. INDEX. A. Absolute, the One Being, 32 f. ; relation of Things to, 33 f. ; Determinations °f. 35 f-I Spinoza's view 0^38; as personal Spirit, 43 f., 55 f., 68; and therefore conscious, 66 f. ; none besides God, 83 f. ; course of the world related to, U4f. Action, between elements, 25 f. ; of Things on each other, 30 f. Argument, the Ontological, 8 f. ; the Cosmological, lof. ; the Teleological. Attributes, of God, 45 f. B. Being, God as the Most Perfect, 9 f. ; as the necessary, 10 f. ; and uncon ditioned, 13 f., 55 f. ; intelligent, 21 ; the Absolute, 32 f. ; Unity of, 52 f. Blessedness, as the supreme end, n8f. C. Christ, as Son of God, 150 f. ; relation to humanity, 150. Church, visible and invisible, 153 ; relation of, to State, 153. Conscience, function of, 129 f.; development of, 131 f. Consciousness, belongs to Personality, 56 f. ; conception of, 56 ; origin of, 57 f. ; involves self-identical Ego, 59 f., 62 ; feeling necessary to, 60 f. Contingent, events, as, 10 f. Creation, conception of, 71 f. ; Divine will in, 73 f. ; not necessarily deed, 74 f., 79 f. ; " out of Nothing," 79 ; no process of, 79 f. D. Design, conscious in Nature, 17 f. Development, not creation, 71 f., 79. Dogmas, necessity of, 143 f. ; subscription to, 145 ; limits of, 147. Dualism, in philosophy, 39 ; as to origin of evil, 124. I6O INDEX. E. Ego, unites elements, 30; idea of, 59 f., 63, 64; correlative to non-egot62f. End, conformity to an, i6f., iSf. ; in the world's history, inf., 114; the supreme, 115 f., 118. Eschatology, not a matter for speculation, 152. Ethics, relation of, to the idea of value, 117; and of expediency, 132 f. Evil, apologies for, 121 f. ; origin of, 124, 126. F. Faith, as organ of Religion, i f. Fall, conception of a, 126 f. Fanaticism, origin of, 144. Feeling, groups of the religious, 5 f. ; necessary to self-consciousness, 60 f. Fichte, on "world-stuff," 97. Force, conception of, in Nature, 17 f, 20 f.; blind and unconscious, 40. Freedom, a condition of Government, 99; not speculatively defensible, ioof., 102, 106; objections to, 103. G. God, proof of his existence, 8 f. ; ontological argument for, 8 f. ; cosmo- logical argument for, 10 f. ; as unconditioned, 13 f. ; teleological argu ment for, 15 f., 22 f., 24 f. ; as Supreme Intelligence, 21 ; Unity of, 45 f. ; Unchangeableness of, 46 f., 52 f. ; Omnipresence of, 47 f. ; Omnipotence of, 49 f., 86 f., 88 ; Eternity of, 51 f. ; Personality of, 55 f., 68 f. ; as Cre ator, 70, 79; productive will of, 73 f., 79 f., 139; no Principle antecedent to, 82, 90; relation of truth to, 84 f., 91 f. ; government of, 95 f. Good, idea of the highest, 122, 133, 141 ; as compatible with Evil, 124; rela tion to the Divine Will, 138 f. Government, the Divine, 95 f.; conditions of, 98 f., 106; distinguished from Preservation, 107 ; by intervention, 109 f. I. Intelligence, in Nature, 21 ; inhering in Things, 24 f. L. Law, not above Things, 83 ; nor antecedent to God, 83 f., 88 f. Leibnitz, best possible world of, 123. INDEX. l6l M. Materialism, its account of self-consciousness, 57. Matter, contrasted with Spirit, 35 f., 37, 38. Metaphysic, Postulates derived from, 30 f., 52. Miracle, the conception of, 107 f. ; abstract conceivableness of, 108 f. extent not speculatively determined, nof. Mysticism, origin of, 143. N. Nature, elements and forces of, 18 f. ; blind course of, 21 f., 47. Necessary, conception of the, 10, 12 f. O. Omnipotence, meaning of the Divine, 49, 86 f., 88; never in the abstract, 87 f. ; modus agendl of, 122. Ought, idea of the, 135 f. P. Pantheism, 38. Personality, conception of, 55 f. ; of the Absolute, 55, 68 ; a self-conscious ego, 59 f., 62 f., 64 ; perfect only when infinite 68 f. Pessimism, 128. Philosophy, legitimate place of, i f. Power, conception of, 87 f. Preservation, of the World, 81 f., 92 f. ; as new creation, 92 f. Principle, the absolute, 35 ; and the supreme, 149. Providence, in organism, 22 f. R. Season, organ of Religion, i f. ; necessarily self-conscious, 39 f. Redemption, idea of, 151 f. Religion, as related to Reason, if., 6; and scientific cognition, 4f. ; involves experience, 5 ; feelings of, 5 f. ; relation to morals, 129 f. ; first principles of, 137; the Christian, 140; the communion of, 145. Rigorism, an ethical, 116 f. 1 62 INDEX. S. Schelling, 38. Science, nature of its cognitions, 4. Sensations, origin of, 36. Sin, origin of, in a Fall, iz.6 f. Spinoza, 38. Spirit, contrasted with Matter, 35 f., 38; always self-conscious, 39, 56 f . ; and personal, 41 f. ; the Infinite, 66; finite spirits, 67 f., 96. Spiritualism, the philosophical, 39. Stoicism, its wise man, 136. T. Theology, relation to philosophy, 148. Things, properties of, 16 f. ; as intelligent, 24 f. ; homogeneous and con nected, 29 f., 31 ; influence of, on each other, 30 f. ; as modifications of the Absolute, 32^,34,67; spiritual susceptibility of, 37; cannot have unity, 53 ; as subject to law, 83. Time, not self-subsisting form, 51 f. Trinity, doctrine of, 149. Truth, as related to God, 84 f., 91 f. U. Unconditioned, conception of the, 13 f. Universe, origin of, 17 f., 28; elements of, 27 f., 28 f. W. Will, the Divine in creation, 73 f. ; the human, 75, 104 ; modus agendi unknown, 77 ; the free, 104 f. World, relation of, to God, 70, 81, 94, 95. Philosophy. Empirical Psychology ; or, The Human Mind as Given in Consciousness. By LAUKENS P. HICKOK, D.D., LL.D. Revised with the cooperation of JULIUS H. SEELYE, D.D., LL.D., President of Amherst College. i2mo. 300 pages. Mailing Price, $1.25 ; Introduction, $1.12; Allowance, 40 cts. Hickok's "Science of the Mind," which has been in the hands of teachers and students for more than a quarter of a century, has been here wholly revised, and almost wholly re-written, making it not only a new text-book but a new contribution to the important science of which it treats. The precision of statement and thorough ness of treatment which so remarkably characterized the original wojk, and made it so highly prized by so many teachers, are no less conspicuous in the present work ; but a different method in the gen eral discussion has been adopted, though the end originally sought is the same. The publishers believe that the book will be found to be remark ably comprehensive, and at the same time compact and clear. It gives a complete outline of the Science, concisely presented, and in precise and plain terms. John Bascom, Pres. of Univ. of Wisconsin, Madison : It is an excellent book. It has done much good service, and, as revised by President Seelyc, is prepared to do much more. (Fel>.^'&2.) I. W. Andrews, Pres. Marietta Coll., Ohio : I am glad to see that this work holds its place among our text books on that most important subject. Dr. Hickok I regard as one of the ablest of our philosophical writers, and few teachers have had so large and success ful an experience as President Seelye. This new edition, carefully revised by these two gentlemen, may be confi dently recommended as presenting a delineation of the mental faculties so clear and accurate that the careful stu dent will hardly fail to recognize its truth in his own experience. (April 6, 1882.) M. Valentine, Pres. and Prof, of Intellectual and Moral Science, Pennsyl vania Coll., Gettysburg : I take pleasure in saying that the new edition impresses me very favorably. This work of Dr. Hickok is unquestionably One of high ability and much merit, and, by its close analysis and compact, orderly classifical of the mind's powers, admirably suited for use as a text-book. Its value is in creased in this edition. (Jan. 28, '82.) 242 PHILOSOPHY. Hichoh's Moral Science. By LAURENS P. HICKOK, D.D., LL.D. Revised with the cooperation of JULIUS H. SEELYE, D.D., LL.D., President of Amherst College. I2mo. Cloth. 288 pages. Mailing price, $1.25; Introduction, $1.12; Allowance, 40 cents. This work is an entire and careful revision of Hickok's original text-book of Moral Science. The remarkable excellences of that book, unsurpassed as it is in systematic rigor and scientific precision, are carefully retained in the present edition. Many parts of the book have, however, been rewritten entirely, modifying the original statements where this was necessary for clearness, and adding new discussions where this was required for fulness. To the many teachers who have used the original text-book with such signal profit, the publishers confidently commend this new and revised edi tion ; and with equal confidence they offer it to others who would like a manual in which the principles of morality are expounded in a manner as truly simple as it is thoroughly scientific. A. P. Peabody, Prof, of Christian Morals, Harvard Coll. : Permit me to express my very high appreciation of the value of the work. I read it when it first appeared with the greatest in terest and satisfaction, and in its pres ent form it possesses whatever added claims the most skilful and careful editorship can give. Had it appeared a month earlier, should more probably than not have adopted it. G. P. Fisher, Prof, of Church His tory, Yale Coll. : I have long wanted to see just such a book, — one in which practical ethics should be clearly and systematically and philosophically pre sented. I am very much pleased with the chapters relating to duties, and not less so with the more theoretical por tion of the work. The style is so per spicuous, ajid at the same time so concise, that the work is eminently adapted to serve as a text-book in col leges and higher schools. In matter and manner it is a capital book, and I wish it God speed. C. B. Hulbert, Pres. Middlebury Coll., Vt., and Prof, of Moral Science : In its present form it is the best of recently issued text-books on Moral Science. A. A. E. Taylor, Pres. of Univ. of Wooster, Ohio, and Prof, of Biblical Instruction : It is a capital text-book for the class-room, fully abreast of the ethical controversies of the day. I. "W. Andrews, Pres. Marietta Coll., O., and Prof, of Intellectual Phi losophy : It is sound, strong, and clear. I doubt whether any work on Moral Science surpasses this in the depth and permanence of the impression made upon the student. It requires study, of course, but it will repay the student, whether teacher or pupil. The part on duties to the State is admirable for its fulness and precision. Wm. F. Swahlen, Pres. McKen- dree Coll., Lebanon, III. : I am more and more pleased with it. PHILOSOPHY. 243 The N. E. Journal of Educa tion : Taken altogether, it is an ad mirable text-book, and we can cor dially recommend it for use wherever pupils are old enough to consider mor ality in a scientific way, or to discuss intelligently the fundamental principles of civil government. No subjects are more vitally necessary in public educa tion, and this volume presents them in a clear, compact, and forcible man- Rational Psychology; or, The Subjective Idea and Objective Law of all Intelligence. By LAURENS P. HiCKOK, D.D., LL.D. 543 pages. 8vo. Mailing Price, $1.95. Introduction, $ 1.80. Creator and Creation ; or, The Knowledge in the Reason of God and His Work. By LAURENS P. HICKOK, £>.D., LL.D. 360 pages. 8vo. Mailing Price, $1.75. Introduction, $i. 60. The Logic of Reason, Universal and Eternal. By LAURENS P. HICKOK, D.D., LL.D. 192 pages. 8vo. Mailing Price, $1.60. Introduction, $1.44. Humanity Immortal ; or, Man Tried, Fallen, and Redeemed. By LAURENS P. HICKOK, D.D., LL.D. 362 pages. 8vo. Mailing Price, #1.75. Introduction, $1.60. These books discuss the most difficult and important problems of human thought. Though each is complete in itself, they pursue the following order : — The EMPIRICAL PSYCHOLOGY gives the basis of all physical and logical science. The RATIONAL PSYCHOLOGY connects all science with philosophy. The CREATOR AND CREATION gives the philosophy of all mechan ical and vital forces. The MORAL SCIENCE is already in the field of philosophy, and gives the basis of ^Esthetics, Politics. Ethics, and Theology. The LOGIC OF REASON frees empiricism from all scepticism in the attainment of a Being absolutely Universal and Eternal. The HUMANITY IMMORTAL gives the Divine history of human experience from its origination to its consummation. 244 PHILOSOPHY. Lotze's Philosophical Outlines. Dictated Portions of the Latest Lectures (at Gottingen and Berlin) of Hermann Lotze. Translated and edited by GEORGE T. LADD, Pro fessor of Philosophy in Yale College. I2mo. Cloth. About 180 pages in each volume. Mailing price per vol., $1.00; Introd. price, 80 cents. The German from which the translations are made consists of the dictated portions of his latest lectures (at Gottingen, and for a few months at Berlin) as formulated by Lotze himself, recorded in the notes of his hearers, and subjected to the most competent and thor ough revision of Professor Rehnisch of Gottingen. The " Outlines " give, therefore, a mature and trustworthy statement, in language selected by this teacher of philosophy himself, of what may be con sidered as his final opinions upon a wide range of subjects. They have met with no little favor in Germany. There is scarcely any other recent writer on philosophical sub jects whose thoughts are so stimulating for their breadth, penetra tion, and candor ; or with whom an acquaintance is so desirable for purposes of general culture through the philosophic way of consid ering life, with its interests in not merely pure thought, but also in morals, religion, and art. It is also hoped that the use of these translations will further the work of teaching philosophy. Such condensed, orderly, and mature statements of conclusions on a wide range of philosophical questions will be found exceedingly valuable for both teacher and pupil. They furnish a scheme for all the instruction which the teacher is able to give in presenting and answering these questions. When skilfully used, they may be made to introduce the pupil to the widest fields of philosophy under the guidance of a great master, and in an inter esting way. They present the applications of Metaphysic to art, religion, nature, and human conduct; — and they thus open regions of reflection into which the instruction of our colleges and universi ties scarcely takes their students at all, — regions, however, which are precisely the ones where such students both desire and need to go. These translations have been undertaken with the kind permission of the German publisher, Herr S. Hirzel, of Leipsic. Outlines of Metaphysic. The Outlines of Metaphysic contajn.s the scientific treatment of PHILOSOPHY. 245 those assumptions which enter into all our cognition of Reality. It consists of three parts, — Ontology, Cosmology, Phenomenology. The first part contains chapters on the Conception of Being, the Content of the Existent, Reality, Change, and Causation ; the second treats of Space, Time, Motion, Matter, and the Coherency of Natural Events ; the third, of the Subjectivity and Objectivity of Cognition. The Metaphysic of Lotze gives the key to his entire philosophical system. It should therefore be studied at the very entrance upon examination of that system. , Outlines of the Philosophy of Religion. In the Outlines of the Philosophy of Religion Lotze seeks " to ascertain how much of the Content of Religion may be discovered, proved, or at least confirmed, agreeably to reason." In successive chapters he discusses the Proof for the Existence of God, the Attri butes and Personality of the Absolute, the Conceptions of the Crea tion, the Preservation, and the Government, of the World, and of the World-time. The book closes with brief discussions of Religion and Morality, and Dogmas and Confessions. Outlines of Practical Philosophy. This one of the " Outlines " contains a discussion of Ethical Principles, Moral Ideals, and the Freedom of the Will, and then an application of the theory to the Individual, to Marriage, to Society, and to the State. Many interesting remarks on Divorce, Socialism, Representative Government, etc., abound throughout the volume. Its style is more popular than that of the other works of Lotze, and it will doubtless be widely read. Outlines of Psychology. The Outlines of Psychology treats of Simple Sensations, the Course of Representative Ideas, of Attention and Inference, of Intuitions of Objects as in Space, of the Apprehension of the Exter nal World by the Senses, of Errors of the Senses, of Feelings, and of Bodily Motions. Its second part is " theoretical," and discusses the nature, position, and changeable states of the Soul, its relations to time, and the reciprocal action of Soul and Body. It closes with a chapter on the " Kingdom of Souls." Lotze is peculiarly rich and suggestive in the discussion of Psychology. 246 PHILOSOPHY. Outlines of /Esthetics. The Outlines of ^Esthetics treats of the theory of the Beautiful and of Phantasy, and of the Realization and different Species of the Beautiful. Then follow brief chapters on Music, Architecture, Plastic Art, Painting, and Poetry. An appendix to this volume contains a brief biography of Lotze. This volume will be of the same size as those issued already. [Ready in 1886. Outlines of Logic. The Outlines of Logic discusses both pure and applied Logic. Under the first head come the formation of Concepts, the theory of Judgment, a system of the forms of Judgment, the doctrine of argu ment or the drawing of conclusions, the figures of Aristotle, etc. The applied Logic presents the application of the forms of Concep tion, the adducing of Proof, and the Process of Thought in Dis covery. The Logic is followed by a brief treatise on the Encyclo paedia of Philosophy, in which are set forth the definition and method of Theoretical Philosophy, of Practical Philosophy, and of the Philosophy of Religion. This volume will be about one-fifth larger than the others, and will make an admirable brief text-book in Logic. W. T. Harris, Concord, Mass. : The project of Prof. Ladd strikes me as by all means a practical one. I think this likely to be the most successful venture in philosophical publication that I have heard of lately. John Bascom, Prfs. of Univ. of Wis. : The publication of this book, and of the promised series, is very desirable. Wm. F. Warren, Pres. Boston University, in the " Western Christian Advocate ": Prof. Ladd is rendering the English-reading public a great service by bringing out in neat and correct form translations of the dictated por tions of the late Professor Hermann Lotze's lectures. Noah K. Davis, Prof, of Moral PAil., Univ. of Vir. : I have desired \Ready in 1886. very much for the use of my pupils, who do not read German, a good trans lation of Lotze's " Dictate " ever since they began to appear. The piesent translation leaves nothing to be desired, except the completion of the series. D. S. Gregory, Pres. Lake Forest (III.) Univ. : Lotze's Outlines of Psy chology will give the young men a comprehensive grasp of all the capital questions at the basis of the current psy chological discussions, and help them to estimate for themselves the real sci entific standing of the prevalent sensa tional psychology. The work of the translator is admirably done, in conse quence of his being able to enter into the thought of the author. W. D.Wilson, Cornell Univ., N. Y.: I have for a long time regarded Lotze PHILOSOPHY. 247 as the soundest, as well as the pro- foundest, of all the German metaphy sicians. H. N. Gardner, Prof, of Philosophy, Smith College : I have -decided to use the Philosophy of Religion next term in the College. John "Watson, Prof. Philosophy, Univ. of Kingston, Can. : I think that judiciously used, it would form a very good transition from the study of Kant to the study of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, especially the last. The Critic, New York: The in fluence of Lotze would be most salu tary in this country at the present time, and many would find in him the phil osophic guide they need. His recon ciliation between science and phil osophy, or between materialism and idealism, is of great importance. To many it will commend itself as the only way out of the philosophic confusion of the present time. The student will find much crowded into a few pages, but Lotze has the merit of clearness. New Englander : The translation of the volume before us is marked by that carefulness, accuracy, and thor oughness that characterize all of Prof. Ladd's work. The task he has accom plished was by no means a slight one, as those familiar with the German of Lotze will recognize ; and if the Eng lish reader still finds difficulties in the way of a clear apprehension of the teaching of Lotze, we must remind him that these difficulties cannot be re moved by a translation, however excel lent it may be. Literary "World, Boston : Pro fessor Ladd has done a great service to all those persons who are interested in the vital questions of the present day, but who are not sufficiently familiar with German to make it easy to read, in the original tongue, one of the freshest and most profound of modern thinkers. We have not found ourselves able to agree with Lotze in all his doctrines ; but have so greatly admired both the candor and the acute profundity of his thought, that we disagree with him modestly, with the concession that he is possibly right when we think him wrong. In the great main trend of his thought we hold him to be certainly right. Mind, London, Eng. : No words are needed to commend such an enter prise, now that Lotze's importance as a thinker is so well understood. The translation is careful and painstaking. Unitarian Review, Boston : We have already called attention to the admirable service Prof. Ladd is ren dering students of philosophy by editing these dictated portions of the lectures of Hermann Lotze. This volume of Outlines is of great interest and sug- gestiveness. It is clear in vision and strong. While we have not accepted the au thor's reasoning as a whole, we have found it remarkably suggestive and stimulating. University, Chicago : It is this union in Lotze of scientific spirit, on the one hand, and of deep regard for the fundamental interests of man, on the other, that makes Lotze so signifi cant a figure in philosophy at present, and the study of him so hopeful a sign. We know of no book of 150 pages that contains more condensed food for thought, or more pregnant statement of informing truth on the higher themes of man's life than these Outlines of the Philosophy of Religion. Books on English Literature. INTBOD. PRICE. Allen . . , . Reader's Guide to English History ... $ .25 History Topics 25 Arnold .... English Literature 1.50 Carpenter. . . Anglo-Saxon Grammar 60 English of the XlVth Century 90 Church .... Stories of the Old World 40 (Classics for Children.) Craik .... English of Shakespeare 90 Garnett . . . Beowulf ( Translation) 1.00 Harrison & Sharp : Beowulf (Text and Glossary) .... 1.12 Hudson . . . Harvard Edition of Shakespeare : — 20 Vol. Edition. Cloth, retail .... 25.00 10 Vol. Edition. Cloth, retail .... 20.00 Life, Art, and Characters of Shakespeare. 2 vols. Cloth, retail 4.00 New School Shakespeare. Cloth. Each play .45 Old School Shakespeare, per play ... .20 Expurgated Family Shakespeare .... 10.00 Essays on Education, English Studies, etc. .25 Three Vol. Shakespeare, per voL .... 1.25 Text-Book of Poetry 1.25 Text-Book of Prose 1.25 Pamphlet Selections, Prose and Poetry . .20 Classical English Reader 1.00 Hudson & Lamb : Merchant of Venice 25 (Classics for Children.) Hunt .... Exodus and Daniel 60 Lambert . . . Robinson Crusoe . „ 35 (Classics for Children.) Memory Gems 30 Lounsbury . . Chaucer's Parlament of Foules 50 Minto .... Manual of English Prose Literature ... 2.00 Sprague . . . Selections from Irving { g^ ; ; ; ; 'f. Two Books of Paradise Lost, and Lycldas .45 Thorn .... Two Shakespeare Examinations 45 Yonge .... Scott's Quentin Durward 40 (Classics for Children.) Copies sent to Teachers for Examination, with a vieu> to Introduction, on receipt of Introduction Price. GINN & COMPANY, Publishers, BOSTON, NEW YOKK, AND CHICAGO. 201 L8850 c.1 Lotze # Outlines of the philosophy of religion : 3 0005 02064885 6 201 L885o Lotze Outlines of the philosophy of religion m